27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

170 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

Moreover, the prism experiment shows that the effect does not depend on the<br />

angle <strong>of</strong> incidence and that one refraction is sufficient for its production. Finally,<br />

Descartes calculates from the refractive index <strong>of</strong> rainwater what an observer would<br />

see when light strikes a drop <strong>of</strong> water at varying angles <strong>of</strong> incidence, and finds<br />

that the optimum difference for visibility between incident and refracted rays is<br />

for the former to be viewed at an angle <strong>of</strong> 41°–42° and the latter at an angle <strong>of</strong><br />

51°–52°, 29 which is exactly what the hypothesis predicts.<br />

This procedure is similar to that followed in the Dioptrics, and in some<br />

inspects to that followed in the Geometry. It is above all an exercise in problemsolving,<br />

and the precedent for such an exercise seems to have been developed in<br />

Descartes’s work in mathematics. Indeed, the later parts <strong>of</strong> the Rules turn<br />

towards specifically mathematical considerations, and Rules 16–21 have such<br />

close parallels with the Geometry that one can only conclude that they contain<br />

the early parts <strong>of</strong> that work in an embryonic form. Rule 16 advises us to use ‘the<br />

briefest possible symbols’ in dealing with problems, and one <strong>of</strong> the first things<br />

the Geometry does is to provide us with the algebraic signs necessary for dealing<br />

with geometrical problems. Rule 17 tells us that, in dealing with a new problem,<br />

we must ignore the fact that some terms are known and some unknown; and<br />

again one <strong>of</strong> the first directives in the Geometry is that we label all lines<br />

necessary for the geometrical construction, whether these be known or unknown.<br />

Finally, Rules 18–21 are formulated in almost identical terms in the Geometry. 30<br />

There is something ironic in this, for one would normally associate a<br />

mathematical model with a method which was axiomatic and deductive.<br />

Certainly, if one looks at the great mathematical texts <strong>of</strong> Antiquity —Euclid’s<br />

Elements or Archimedes’s On the Sphere and the Cylinder or Apollonius’s On<br />

Conic Sections, for example—one finds lists <strong>of</strong> definitions and postulates and<br />

deductive pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> theorems relying solely on these. If one now turns to<br />

Descartes’s Geometry, one finds something completely different. After a few<br />

pages <strong>of</strong> introduction, mainly on the geometrical representation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

arithmetical operations <strong>of</strong> multiplication, division and finding roots, we are<br />

thrown into one <strong>of</strong> the great unsolved problems bequeathed by Antiquity—<br />

Pappus’s locus problem for four or more lines, which Descartes then proceeds to<br />

provide us with a method <strong>of</strong> solving.<br />

Descartes’s solution to the Pappus problem is an ‘analytic’ one. In ancient<br />

mathematics, a sharp distinction was made between analysis and synthesis.<br />

Pappus, one <strong>of</strong> the greatest <strong>of</strong> the Alexandrian mathematicians, had distinguished<br />

between two kinds <strong>of</strong> analysis: ‘theoretical’ analysis, in which one attempts to<br />

discover the truth <strong>of</strong> a theorem, and ‘problematical analysis’, in which one<br />

attempts to discover something unknown. If, in the case <strong>of</strong> theoretical analysis,<br />

one finds that the theorem is false or if, in the case <strong>of</strong> problematical analysis, the<br />

proposed procedure fails to yield what one is seeking, or one can show the<br />

problem to be insoluble, then synthesis is not needed, and analysis is complete in<br />

its own right. In the case <strong>of</strong> positive results, however, synthesis is needed, albeit<br />

for different reasons. Synthesis is a difficult notion to specify, and it appears to

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!