27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM 375<br />

which requires that any two minds must be qualitatively, not just numerically,<br />

different. Although Leibniz is not quite explicit about this, another assumption <strong>of</strong><br />

the argument seems to be that minds at or before birth have no conscious<br />

experiences; thus the individuating characteristics required by the identity <strong>of</strong><br />

indiscernibles must occur below the threshold <strong>of</strong> consciousness. 82 Other<br />

arguments are less tied to the distinctive principles <strong>of</strong> Leibniz’s metaphysics, but<br />

not all <strong>of</strong> them are more cogent. Leibniz is fond <strong>of</strong> arguing that, in order to hear<br />

the waves breaking on the shore, we must hear the noise <strong>of</strong> each individual<br />

wave. 83 This argument has been criticized as being as dubious as arguing, from<br />

the fact that we feel the weight <strong>of</strong> a stone, that we must have an unconscious<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> the molecules that make it up. 84<br />

Perhaps more interesting is what we may call Leibniz’s ‘attention argument’<br />

which may be illustrated by the following scenario. 85 Suppose that two people,<br />

Smith and Jones, are having a conversation and that, throughout, a drill has been<br />

operating in the background; Smith has not been conscious <strong>of</strong> the noise, but he<br />

now suddenly has his attention drawn to it by Jones. Leibniz argues that in the act<br />

<strong>of</strong> attention Smith is really remembering a past perception <strong>of</strong> the noise. But ex<br />

hypothesi this earlier perception was not a conscious one and must therefore have<br />

been ‘little’ or unconscious. This argument clearly depends on the premise that<br />

attention involves memory, and one might wonder why one should accept this. If<br />

it is supposed to be true by definition, then the definition seems merely<br />

stipulative. Nonetheless, there is something attractive about the suggestion that<br />

cases like this force us to recognize the existence <strong>of</strong> unconscious perceptions,<br />

and Leibniz can support his conclusion in other ways. For example, it was<br />

implicitly assumed in our description <strong>of</strong> the case that Smith’s sense organs are<br />

equally stimulated by the drilling both before and during the act <strong>of</strong> attention.<br />

Now Leibniz cannot <strong>of</strong> course strictly ascribe any psychological effects to a<br />

physical stimulus, but by virtue <strong>of</strong> his theory <strong>of</strong> expression he can and does insist<br />

that some state <strong>of</strong> the soul must correspond to any such stimulation; 86 and by<br />

hypothesis, as we have seen, the mental state which precedes the act <strong>of</strong> attention<br />

is not a conscious awareness <strong>of</strong> the noise. Leibniz can also fall back on an appeal<br />

to the law <strong>of</strong> continuity; 87 there would be a flagrant breach <strong>of</strong> this law if the<br />

stimulus which ‘produced’ a conscious perception <strong>of</strong> the noise during the act <strong>of</strong><br />

attention ‘produced’ no perception at all in the mind before the act.<br />

The doctrine <strong>of</strong> unconscious perceptions is a key element in Leibniz’s attack<br />

on the Cartesian view that mentality is all or nothing. For Leibniz, by contrast,<br />

mentality is a continuum which extends below the threshold <strong>of</strong> consciousness.<br />

Sometimes, as we should expect, Leibniz’s rejection <strong>of</strong> Descartes’s view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mental life provides the basis for the rejection <strong>of</strong> other Cartesian doctrines.<br />

Leibniz sides with common sense against the notorious Cartesian thesis that<br />

animals are mere automata. He argues that the Cartesians were led astray by their<br />

failure to distinguish between thought and perception; in other words, the<br />

Cartesians have made the mistake <strong>of</strong> confusing a species with its corresponding<br />

genus. 88 Thus even if animals have no thought (cogitatio), it does not follow that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!