27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

226 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

GASSENDI<br />

When Hobbes warns against relying on authors and insists on reaching<br />

conclusions from evident first principles, he may seem to reflect the intellectual<br />

style <strong>of</strong> early modern philosophy better than Gassendi does by his use <strong>of</strong><br />

Epicurus. But this impression may have more to do with a certain kind <strong>of</strong><br />

historiography than with the facts <strong>of</strong> intellectual life in the 1600s. The usual<br />

histories <strong>of</strong> this period <strong>of</strong> philosophy emphasize novelty, revolution and<br />

methodological principles that seem to prepare the way for nineteenth- and<br />

twentieth-century science. Bacon’s, Galileo’s and Descartes’s writings lend<br />

themselves particularly well to this conception <strong>of</strong> a time <strong>of</strong> decisive intellectual<br />

change, a time that ushered in modernity and saw out tradition, and these<br />

writings tend to be discussed to the exclusion <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> other seventeenthcentury<br />

figures—even figures whom the canonical moderns respected and took<br />

for allies, such as Gassendi. The standard histories may not only be criticized for<br />

overlooking the celebrity and influence that Gassendi enjoyed in his own day;<br />

they may not only be criticized for making this celebrity hard to understand once<br />

it is pointed out; they may also be criticized for missing the strengths <strong>of</strong> the<br />

traditional form <strong>of</strong> presentation used by Gassendi in the context <strong>of</strong> the early<br />

seventeenth century.<br />

Many <strong>of</strong> those who promoted the new science and attacked the old philosophy<br />

did so in books that they knew would meet hostility from the church and the<br />

schoolmen. By choosing for some <strong>of</strong> his works the literary form <strong>of</strong> the erudite<br />

rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> an ancient authority like Epicurus, Gassendi was employing the<br />

methods that the doctors <strong>of</strong> the church had used to appropriate Aristotle. Again,<br />

by being comprehensive in his treatment <strong>of</strong> Epicurus’s critics Gassendi gave the<br />

impression <strong>of</strong> being an even-handed exponent <strong>of</strong> his chosen author, in contrast<br />

with sycophantic followers <strong>of</strong> Aristotle. He discussed the views <strong>of</strong> Epicurus in the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> the antagonisms between the ancient Greek schools <strong>of</strong> philosophy,<br />

including the Peripatetics, and so he was able to revive a sense <strong>of</strong> Aristotle and<br />

his school as representing just one way <strong>of</strong> thinking among others during a period<br />

in which Greek philosophy was sectarian, and when no one sect had any special<br />

authority. Again, by showing that the genuine Epicurus had been completely lost<br />

in the lore about Epicurus, Gassendi was able to introduce to intellectual life a<br />

virtually new figure, not just a relatively familiar one who deserved a second<br />

hearing. Apart from the novelty <strong>of</strong> the Epicurus that Gassendi revived, there was<br />

the relevance <strong>of</strong> his views to the topical issues <strong>of</strong> the anomalies in Aristotle’s<br />

physics, and the significance <strong>of</strong> scepticism. In relation to scepticism,<br />

Epicureanism seemed to claim less, and so to be less vulnerable to sceptical<br />

criticism, than Aristotelianism. This was the lesson <strong>of</strong> Gassendi’s exposition <strong>of</strong><br />

Epicurean canonics as a preferred logic. In relation to seventeenth-century<br />

physics, Epicurean explanations avoided some <strong>of</strong> the anomalies that Aristotelian<br />

explanations were increasingly embarrassed by. 5 At the same time, it could be<br />

regarded as a comprehensive natural philosophy.Finally, Gassendi was able to

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!