27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM 17<br />

in holding these erroneous views, but he presented the greatest danger, Petrarch<br />

believed, because he had the most authority and the greatest number <strong>of</strong> followers.<br />

And while the pagan Aristotle could not be blamed for holding these errors, his<br />

present-day acolytes had no excuse. 9<br />

Despite their adulation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle, the scholastics failed, in Petrarch’s<br />

opinion, to understand his thought. They disdained eloquence, treating it as ‘an<br />

obstacle and a disgrace to philosophy’, whereas Aristotle had believed that it was<br />

‘a mighty adornment’. 10 He blamed the inelegant style which characterized Latin<br />

versions <strong>of</strong> Aristotle not on the author’s inattention to style but on the ignorance<br />

<strong>of</strong> his medieval translators—a censure which was to be frequently repeated by<br />

later humanists. 11 Yet aside from the ethical treatises, Petrarch’s acquaintance<br />

with Aristotle’s writings was neither wide nor deep.<br />

If Petrarch was ill-informed about ‘the Philosopher’, he was positively<br />

ignorant about ‘the Commentator’, Averroes, probably never having read<br />

anything at all by him. This did not stop him from criticizing the Arabic<br />

interpreter even more strongly than he had done the Greek philosopher. 12 In<br />

sharp contrast to the scholastics, who considered Arabic learning to be an<br />

important part <strong>of</strong> their intellectual legacy, Petrarch and his humanist successors<br />

restricted their philosophical interests almost exclusively to the Greco-Roman<br />

past. Among the doctrines traditionally associated with Averroism was the<br />

double truth, 13 which theologians such as Thomas Aquinas rejected, maintaining<br />

that there was only one truth, the truth <strong>of</strong> faith, and that any philosophical<br />

proposition which contradicted it was necessarily false. Petrarch shared this<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view, arguing that since ‘knowledge <strong>of</strong> the true faith’ was ‘the highest,<br />

most certain, and ultimately most beatifying <strong>of</strong> all knowledge’, those who<br />

temporarily set it aside, wishing ‘to appear as philosophers rather than as<br />

Christians’, were in reality ‘seeking the truth after having rejected the truth’. 14<br />

According to him, scholastics were forced into this position not by an inevitable<br />

conflict between philosophy and religion, but rather by their support for one<br />

particular philosophy, Aristotelianism, which on certain crucial issues —the<br />

eternity <strong>of</strong> the world and the immortality <strong>of</strong> the soul—denied the fundamental<br />

truths <strong>of</strong> Christianity. The solution was therefore not to abandon philosophy per<br />

se, but to adopt a different sort <strong>of</strong> philosophy, one which avoided these<br />

theological errors.<br />

That philosophy, for Petrarch, was Platonism. Plato, who <strong>of</strong>fered convincing<br />

rational arguments in support <strong>of</strong> both the immortality <strong>of</strong> the soul and the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world, had risen higher ‘in divine matters’ than other pagans. Because<br />

Plato ‘came nearer than all the others’ to Christian truth, he, and not his student<br />

Aristotle, deserved to be called ‘the prince <strong>of</strong> philosophy’. By promoting Plato as<br />

a more theologically correct, and hence more pr<strong>of</strong>ound, philosopher than<br />

Aristotle, Petrarch was able to mount yet another challenge to the scholastic<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> his day. 15 But for all his advocacy <strong>of</strong> Plato, Petrarch’s knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> his works—like that <strong>of</strong> all Western scholars in this period—was very limited.<br />

Of the four dialogues then available in Latin, he made extensive use only <strong>of</strong> the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!