27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

260 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

That this is Spinoza’s view <strong>of</strong> the geometrical method is confirmed by his use<br />

<strong>of</strong> definitions in the Ethics. 31 These definitions are usually stated in the form,<br />

‘By…I understand…’; and this raises a problem. Spinoza is in effect saying that<br />

he proposes to take a term in such and such a way. Such definitions seem to be<br />

<strong>of</strong> the kind that is commonly called ‘stipulative’, and it is now usually held that<br />

(in the words <strong>of</strong> a modern textbook <strong>of</strong> logic) ‘a stipulative definition is neither<br />

true nor false, but should be regarded as a proposal or resolution to use the<br />

definiendum to mean what is meant by the definiens, or as a request or<br />

command’. 32 Given that that is so, one may ask why one should accept Spinoza’s<br />

definitions. Why should we use words in the way that he tacitly requests or<br />

commands? Why play one particular language game, rather than another?<br />

To answer this question, it will be useful to consider first what Spinoza is<br />

excluding when he states his definitions. The terms that he defines are not words<br />

that he has invented; he uses terms that others had used, but he <strong>of</strong>ten uses them in<br />

a new way. So when he says something <strong>of</strong> the form ‘By…I understand…’, he is<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten excluding what some, and perhaps most, philosophers understood by the<br />

term defined. His reason for rejecting such definitions, and for defining terms in<br />

the way that he does, is made clear in the course <strong>of</strong> the definitions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

emotions in Part III <strong>of</strong> the Ethics. Here, Spinoza says that ‘It is my purpose to<br />

explain, not the meanings <strong>of</strong> words, but the nature <strong>of</strong> things.’ 33 What he is doing<br />

when he defines terms has a parallel in the practice <strong>of</strong> scientists, who sometimes<br />

coin completely new terms and sometimes use old terms in a new way—as when<br />

a scientist uses the word Velocity’ to mean, not just speed, but speed in a certain<br />

direction. 34<br />

Definitions form an integral part <strong>of</strong> the geometrical method, so what has just<br />

been said confirms the view suggested earlier: namely, that Spinoza uses the<br />

geometrical method not just to establish truths, but also to explain, to achieve<br />

understanding. This point will meet us again when we consider the distinctive<br />

way in which Spinoza uses the terms ‘true’ and ‘false’ (see pp. 296–7). At<br />

present, however, there is a further question to be raised. The idea that deductive<br />

reasoning can be used to provide explanations was by no means new with<br />

Spinoza, or indeed in the seventeenth century in general; on the contrary, it can<br />

be traced back as far as Aristotle. In the Posterior Analytics (I 13, 78 a38–b3)<br />

Aristotle explains the fact that all planets shine steadily by presenting it as the<br />

conclusion <strong>of</strong> a deductive, or more precisely a syllogistic, argument. 35 This raises<br />

the question why Spinoza should have chosen to present his explanatory system<br />

in geometrical, rather than in syllogistic, form. The answer must surely be that he<br />

was influenced by the new science <strong>of</strong> his time. For this science, mathematics was<br />

the key to the understanding <strong>of</strong> nature. So, for example, Descartes had declared<br />

in his Principles <strong>of</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> (Pt II, 64; CSM i, 247) that the only principles<br />

that he required in physics were those <strong>of</strong> geometry and pure mathematics; to this<br />

one may add Spinoza’s observation, made in the Appendix to Part I <strong>of</strong> the Ethics<br />

(G i, 79), that truth might have lain hidden from the human race through all eternity<br />

had it not been for mathematics. As to the possibility <strong>of</strong> an explanatory system

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!