27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA 297<br />

State’, the then minor William III, should never become a stadholder in the<br />

Republic. But also he was convinced that the regenten were too keen on<br />

‘warming themselves at the coals’ <strong>of</strong> the burning houses <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

SPINOZA’S POSITION<br />

Spinoza elaborates his conception <strong>of</strong> morality and politics against the<br />

background <strong>of</strong> his predecessors, using their arguments, examples and concepts.<br />

The result <strong>of</strong> this elaboration is both recognizable and totally different. Spinoza<br />

aims at conceptual integration and reformulates the convictions <strong>of</strong> spirits kindred<br />

to his own so as to adapt them to his own principles. Notwithstanding the evident<br />

ideological preoccupations <strong>of</strong> these authors, Spinoza believed that in all<br />

judgements there is some element <strong>of</strong> truth. We do not correct false statements by<br />

pointing out their falsity, but by improving on their truth, as Spinoza already<br />

explained in his Short Treatise and postulated in E II P35.<br />

Teleology<br />

We have seen how on the foundations <strong>of</strong> the Leiden Neostoic-Aristotelian<br />

tradition, Velthuysen gave teleology a central place in his moral and political<br />

thought. Spinoza reacts at length to this notion. In E I App, he explains that the<br />

teleological conception <strong>of</strong> nature is a projection <strong>of</strong> man, who takes his own goaloriented<br />

behaviour as a paradigm, unconscious <strong>of</strong> the fact that in reality<br />

everything happens according to causality. This projection leads to awkward<br />

consequences: ‘But while they sought to show that nature does nothing in vain<br />

(i.e. nothing which is not <strong>of</strong> use to men), they seem to have shown only that<br />

nature and the Gods are as mad as men.’ Indeed, nature has also provided many<br />

inconveniences (storms, earthquakes, diseases etc.) and they are imputed to the<br />

Gods being angry with men. Man may see himself as the maker <strong>of</strong> things (e.g. a<br />

house) and even form universal ideas or models to which these things have to<br />

conform, but this does not apply to nature.<br />

The reason, therefore, or cause, why God, or Nature, acts, and the reason<br />

why he exists, are one and the same. As he exists for the sake <strong>of</strong> no end, he<br />

also acts for the sake <strong>of</strong> no end. Rather, as he has no principle or end <strong>of</strong><br />

existing, so he has also none <strong>of</strong> acting. What is called a final cause is<br />

nothing but a human appetite ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is considered as a principal, or<br />

primary cause, <strong>of</strong> some thing.<br />

(E <strong>IV</strong> Praef)<br />

This is typically Spinozistic argumentation. An opinion or imagination is<br />

reinterpreted in terms <strong>of</strong> a more general theory. The opinion is not denied, but<br />

restricted in its applicability. These opinions cannot be taken as knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

nature, because they are a consequence or part <strong>of</strong> nature.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!