27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Physics<br />

GASSENDI AND HOBBES 231<br />

Gassendi’s physics begins with questions about the number <strong>of</strong> worlds, the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> the world-soul and the known locations <strong>of</strong> the known parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. This helps to define in a preliminary way the scheme <strong>of</strong> nature that<br />

physics is concerned with. He goes on to consider the metaphysical status <strong>of</strong><br />

place and time. From Galileo’s results concerning falling bodies he knew that<br />

physical effects could be a function <strong>of</strong> elapsed time or space traversed, and yet<br />

none <strong>of</strong> the traditional categories for real things—substance, attribute, corporeal<br />

or incorporeal —seemed to classify place and time adequately: Gassendi opens his<br />

physics with reasons why the traditional categories are unsuitable and reasons<br />

why place and space and duration are real and similar in their incorporeal<br />

natures. He then tries to play down his evident departure from Aristotelian<br />

physics by saying that what he calls space is just the same as ‘that space which is<br />

generally called imaginary and which the majority <strong>of</strong> sacred doctors admit exists<br />

beyond the universe’ (Book II, ch. 1, Brush, 389). By ‘imaginary’ he does not<br />

mean fictional. Rather, as he explains, he means something that it takes<br />

imagination, and in particular the power the imagination has <strong>of</strong> constructing<br />

analogues <strong>of</strong> the space it senses, to conceive. The power <strong>of</strong> making analogues<br />

is mentioned in Part One <strong>of</strong> Institutio Logica (canon 3) and consists <strong>of</strong> forming a<br />

likeness to something borne in by the senses.<br />

Section One <strong>of</strong> the physics continues with the exposition <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong><br />

competing theories <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the matter <strong>of</strong> the universe, culminating in the<br />

acceptance <strong>of</strong> a revised Epicurean atomism in Book III, ch. 8. The chapter starts<br />

with a list <strong>of</strong> departures from Epicurus. Although Gassendi agrees that ‘the<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> the world and <strong>of</strong> all the things in it is made up <strong>of</strong> atoms’ (Brush, 398),<br />

he denies all <strong>of</strong> the following: that the atoms are eternal; that they are uncreated;<br />

that they are infinite in number, capable <strong>of</strong> being any shape, and self-moving<br />

(ibid., 399). He claims instead that ‘atoms are the primary form <strong>of</strong> matter, which<br />

God created finite from the beginning, which he formed into this visible world,<br />

which, finally, he ordained and permitted to undergo transformations out <strong>of</strong><br />

which, in short, all the bodies which exist in the universe are composed ’ (ibid.,<br />

399).<br />

He conceives matter not in Cartesian fashion as extension in three dimensions<br />

simply, but as solid or <strong>of</strong>fering resistance. Atoms are indivisible particles <strong>of</strong><br />

matter. To the question <strong>of</strong> whether a physical indivisible is conceivable, given<br />

that whatever is physical would seem to have parts, Gassendi generally replies by<br />

drawing an analogy between a physical minimum and minimum sensible.<br />

Something so small as to be at the limit <strong>of</strong> what the human eye can register—<br />

Gassendi’s example is the itch mite—can nevertheless be conceived to have a<br />

surface made up <strong>of</strong> indefinitely many physical parts—atoms, say. This does not<br />

take away its claim to be the smallest visible thing; similarly, the fact that it is<br />

possible to think <strong>of</strong> the atom’s extremities matched one to one with indefinitely<br />

many geometrical points does not take away its status as the smallest physical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!