27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

8 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

Given a knowledge <strong>of</strong> the existence and nature <strong>of</strong> the supreme being, the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rationalist was, as it were, to build on this foundation by deriving the<br />

consequences which followed. But there were important differences between the<br />

ways in which the seventeenth-century rationalists saw this being. For all <strong>of</strong> them<br />

except Spinoza, the supreme being was a personal deity, creator <strong>of</strong> the universe,<br />

and choos ing freely to create it. Spinoza argued that such a concept was<br />

incoherent, and that a consistent account <strong>of</strong> the necessary being must present it<br />

as an impersonal being, within which particular things exist, and which cannot<br />

rationally be regarded as exercising free will. This was clearly opposed to<br />

orthodox Christian doctrine; however, one should not exaggerate Spinoza’s role<br />

in ending the predominance <strong>of</strong> Christian ideas in philosophy. 36 His philosophy,<br />

at first bitterly attacked, was later largely forgotten until its revival by the<br />

German romantics towards the end <strong>of</strong> the eighteenth century. A more important<br />

factor in the loosening <strong>of</strong> the ties between Christianity and philosophy was the<br />

rise in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries <strong>of</strong> deism; that is, <strong>of</strong> belief in a<br />

creative deity, unaccompanied by any belief in a divine revelation. With this,<br />

rationalism had little to do. 37<br />

Today, there is widespread agreement that the seventeenth-century rationalists<br />

failed to provide an a priori pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> God, however that God<br />

was conceived by them. It would also be agreed that they failed to find, by pure<br />

reason, necessary connections between the nature <strong>of</strong> God and the laws <strong>of</strong> science. 38<br />

But these failures do not deprive their philosophy <strong>of</strong> all value. For them, science<br />

was not merely something that had to be justified; it was also something that<br />

posed problems, and their attempts to solve these problems are still found<br />

interesting.<br />

The question whether human beings can strictly speaking be called free had<br />

long exercised philosophers. Before the seventeenth century, the problem took a<br />

theological form. Philosophers, such as Boethius in the sixth century AD and<br />

Lorenzo Valla in the fifteenth, asked how human freedom could be consistent<br />

with the foreknowledge and providence <strong>of</strong> God. These problems continued to be<br />

discussed in the seventeenth century, but in that era there was a new problem <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. For the new science, all physical events were determined by necessary<br />

laws; so the question arose how there could be any human freedom, given that<br />

we are (even if only in part) physical objects. Spinoza and Leibniz <strong>of</strong>fered<br />

solutions which took the form <strong>of</strong> what are now called ‘compatibilist’ theories,<br />

arguing, in very different ways, that freedom and determinism can be<br />

reconciled. 39<br />

Science posed another problem for the seventeenth-century rationalist. One <strong>of</strong><br />

Descartes’s best known theses is his view that mind and body are ‘really<br />

distinct’, that is, that each can exist without the other. Behind this, there lay a<br />

view about scientific explanation: namely, that bodies are to be understood solely<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> physical concepts, and minds solely in terms <strong>of</strong> mental concepts. 40 To<br />

explain physical events, therefore, we do not need to postulate the intervention <strong>of</strong><br />

incorporeal agents (such as, for example, the planetary intelligences). But this

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!