27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

208 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

Descartes’s way round this impasse is to invoke an innate, divinely ordained,<br />

power <strong>of</strong> the human mind. In creating the human soul, God structured it in such a<br />

way that various sensory experiences will ‘arise’ in it whenever the body to<br />

which it is united is stimulated in a certain way. Thus, the mind has the innate<br />

capacity <strong>of</strong> ‘representing colours to itself on the occasion <strong>of</strong> certain corporeal<br />

motions [in the brain]’. There is, in effect, no genuine causal transmission<br />

between mind and body; ‘nothing reaches the mind from external objects except<br />

corporeal motions’; we make judgements about external things ‘not because<br />

these things transmit ideas to our mind through the sense organs, but because<br />

they transmit something which, at exactly the right moment, gives the mind the<br />

occasion to form these ideas by means <strong>of</strong> the faculty innate to it.’ 104 What we<br />

have here is something powerfully reminiscent <strong>of</strong> developments later in the<br />

seventeenth century—the occasionalism <strong>of</strong> Malebranche, and the Leibnizian<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> ‘pre-established harmony’. And the lesson to be learned from this is<br />

that the ideas <strong>of</strong> Malebranche and Leibniz were not, as is sometimes suggested,<br />

bizarre attempts to cobble together an ad hoc solution to the problem <strong>of</strong> mindbody<br />

interaction which Descartes had bequeathed to Western philosophy; rather,<br />

they take their cue from Descartes’s own terminology, and his insistence that the<br />

relationship between physical events and mental phenomena must be explained<br />

on the model <strong>of</strong> divinely decreed correlations rather than transparent causal<br />

transactions. The heterogeneous worlds <strong>of</strong> mind and matter cannot, properly<br />

speaking, interact; only the decrees <strong>of</strong> God can ensure that they work<br />

harmoniously together.<br />

To conclude from this that Descartes’s theory <strong>of</strong> the mind is a failure would be<br />

easy enough; but any sense <strong>of</strong> superiority that the modern commentator may feel<br />

should be tempered by the thought that, even today, the relationship between<br />

brain occurrences and conscious experience is very far from having been<br />

elucidated in a coherent and philosophically satisfying way. What may be a more<br />

fruitful theme for reflection is Descartes’s own implicit recognition <strong>of</strong> the limits<br />

<strong>of</strong> human knowledge. The Cartesian project for a unified system <strong>of</strong> knowledge,<br />

founded on transparently clear first principles, faltered, as we saw in the first half<br />

<strong>of</strong> this chapter, when the human mind came to confront the incomprehensible<br />

greatness <strong>of</strong> God. And in a different way, the project faltered when it came to<br />

integrating into science that most basic fact <strong>of</strong> human awareness—our everyday<br />

experience, through our external and internal senses, <strong>of</strong> the world around us and<br />

the condition <strong>of</strong> our bodies. To ‘explain’ that awareness, Descartes was<br />

constrained to admit that only the decrees <strong>of</strong> God, ultimately opaque to human<br />

reason, will suffice. Causal transparency gives way to mere regular conjunction.<br />

If this, once again, seems to prefigure the thought <strong>of</strong> Hume, that should perhaps<br />

be no surprise. For however much commentators may wish to present it as a<br />

contest between opposing teams <strong>of</strong> ‘rationalists’ and ‘empiricists’, the history <strong>of</strong><br />

the early modern period is a continuous unfolding tapestry in which the threads<br />

endlessly cross and re-cross. The picture that has come down to us is the work <strong>of</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!