27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

DESCARTES: METAPHYSICS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 189<br />

1610s, and we know from his letters that a great inspiration during his early<br />

years was the Dutch mathematician Isaac Beeckman, whom he met in Holland in<br />

1618. Beeckman seems to have played for Descartes something <strong>of</strong> the role which<br />

Hume was later to play for Kant—waking him from his dogmatic slumbers: ‘you<br />

alone roused me from my state <strong>of</strong> indolence’ wrote Descartes to Beeckman on 23<br />

April 1619 ‘and reawakened the learning that by then had almost disappeared<br />

from my mind’. 12 One <strong>of</strong> the chief points to strike Descartes was that<br />

mathematics could attain complete clarity and precision in its arguments, and<br />

that the demonstrations it employed were completely certain: no room was<br />

allowed for merely probabilistic reasoning. 13 The mathematical model continued<br />

to influence his scientific work throughout the following decade, 14 leading up to<br />

the composition <strong>of</strong> his treatise on physics and cosmology, Le Monde, which<br />

announced, at any rate in outline, a comprehensive programme for the<br />

elimination <strong>of</strong> qualitative descriptions from science in favour <strong>of</strong> exact<br />

quantitative analysis. 15<br />

Even in this early period, however, Descartes’s interests were never purely<br />

scientific (in the restricted modern sense): right from the start he seems to have<br />

been concerned with how the results achieved in mathematics and physics were<br />

to be related to more fundamental issues about the nature and basis <strong>of</strong> human<br />

knowledge. In his Regulae ad directionem ingenii (‘Rules for the Direction <strong>of</strong> our<br />

Native Intelligence’, written in Latin in the late 1620s but not published during<br />

his lifetime), Descartes makes it clear that his interest in subjects like geometry<br />

and arithmetic derives in large part from the fact that they are merely examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> a more general procedure <strong>of</strong> potentially universal application:<br />

I came to see that the exclusive concern <strong>of</strong> mathematics is with questions <strong>of</strong><br />

order or measure, and that it is irrelevant whether the measure in question<br />

involves numbers, shapes, stars, sounds or any other object whatever. This<br />

made me realize that there must be a general science which explains all the<br />

points that can be raised concerning order and measure, irrespective <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subject-matter, and that this science deserves to be called mathesis<br />

universalis. 16<br />

It is important to note that the ‘universal discipline’ described here does not<br />

merely encompass quantitative subject matter. Descartes believes that there is a<br />

formal structure which all valid systems <strong>of</strong> knowledge manifest, and that this<br />

structure consists essentially in a hierarchical ordering: the objects <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

are to be arranged in such a way that we can concentrate to begin with on the<br />

items which are ‘simplest and easiest to know’, only afterwards proceeding to<br />

the more complex truths which are derived from these basic starting-points. 17<br />

The human intellect, Descartes goes on to explain, has the power to ‘intuit’ these<br />

‘simple natures’ or fundamental starting-points for human knowledge: it simply<br />

‘sees’ them with a simple and direct mental perception which allows for no

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!