27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

136 FRANCIS BACON AND MAN’S TWO-FACED KINGDOM<br />

vindication <strong>of</strong> a prototype or paradigm <strong>of</strong> knowledge and <strong>of</strong> a criterion to gauge<br />

it that he (unlike other thinkers) nowhere appears to have fully articulated in an<br />

abstract and systematic manner. Yet, Bacon’s starting-point, as revealed by the<br />

rhetorical devices he employs in order to commend his cognitive project and by<br />

the religious mould in which he chooses to cast his programme, is as transparent<br />

as it could be. Most significantly, Bacon contrasts the progress and<br />

perfectiveness <strong>of</strong> human art, as portrayed in technical innovation, with the<br />

stagnation and backwardness <strong>of</strong> philosophy (Parasceve I, 399; <strong>IV</strong>, 257; De<br />

Augmentis II, ch. 2: I, 399f.; <strong>IV</strong>, 297f.). The printing press, the mariner’s<br />

compass and the use <strong>of</strong> gunpowder are not only the indelible marks <strong>of</strong> modernity<br />

but the living pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the fertility <strong>of</strong> the human mind when correctly applied to<br />

those things it is legitimately fit to know or invent. Yet, one should stress here<br />

the tremendous axiological shift that Bacon is silently proposing as his rockbottom<br />

option for, on purely logical grounds, nothing is intrinsically more<br />

‘useful’ than anything else, except with respect to a scale <strong>of</strong> values which, in<br />

itself, ought to remain beyond the very scope <strong>of</strong> discussion about fertility or<br />

sterility. 33<br />

The specific contents <strong>of</strong> a given philosophical discourse may originally<br />

correspond to or be the basis <strong>of</strong> an ideal <strong>of</strong> science which, for a variety <strong>of</strong><br />

reasons, is subsequently forgotten or overshadowed by a competing one. That<br />

Bacon’s insights into the nature <strong>of</strong> human knowledge constitute a coherent type<br />

<strong>of</strong> operativist or constructivist epistemology in the sense enunciated above by no<br />

means implies that the ingredients <strong>of</strong> Bacon’s scientific ideal could not have<br />

been extracted from the original context and taken over by other cognitive<br />

programmes or proposals. Ideas about induction, experiment, mattertheory and<br />

the like belong to this class <strong>of</strong> ingredients, as do in other domains techniques <strong>of</strong><br />

measurement or the register <strong>of</strong> natural constants. The latter build up the specific<br />

‘grammar’ <strong>of</strong> a discourse (i.e. its syntactic rules, its vocabulary and so on),<br />

whilst the former are akin to the general semantics which the text ultimately<br />

appeals to or reveals. Thus, the elementary propositions <strong>of</strong> geometrical optics<br />

(e.g. the laws <strong>of</strong> refraction or reflection) can serve the purposes <strong>of</strong> and be<br />

incorporated into both a corpuscularian and an undulatory theory <strong>of</strong> light.<br />

Likewise, Bacon’s seminal insights about induction or experiment may be<br />

studied, to a large extent at least, independently <strong>of</strong> any discussion about the<br />

maker’s knowledge ideal.<br />

Contrary to a widespread opinion, Francis Bacon was not the first philosopher<br />

who tried to elaborate something akin to a logic <strong>of</strong> induction, and the wealth <strong>of</strong><br />

remarks left by Aristotle on epag g well deserve exposition and comment. 34<br />

The scholastic tradition, by contrast, was more bent on the predominantly<br />

deductive cast <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s mind, and hence the Schoolmen’s references to<br />

induction are both repetitive and shallow. 35 In brief, they distinguished between a<br />

so-called inductio perfecta, which enumerated all the particulars under<br />

consideration, and an inductio imperfecta, which omitted some <strong>of</strong> them and<br />

therefore was liable to be overthrown by any contradictory instance. In neither

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!