27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

356 LEIBNIZ: TRUTH, KNOWLEDGE AND METAPHYSICS<br />

ascribe modes and states to the composing entities without any need to<br />

refer to the aggregate itself. 8<br />

Thus, a proposition such as ‘The army fought bravely’ is reducible to<br />

propositions which ascribe various properties to the members <strong>of</strong> the aggregate,<br />

namely, the individual soldiers.<br />

Perhaps more controversial is the second premise <strong>of</strong> the argument. A nonorganic<br />

body such as a block <strong>of</strong> marble does not seem to be on a par with clearcut<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> aggregates such as an army or a flock <strong>of</strong> sheep. Leibniz must<br />

admit that a block <strong>of</strong> marble is more tightly bonded than these aggregates, but he<br />

would claim that this fact is not metaphysically significant; a block <strong>of</strong> marble is<br />

no less an entity by aggregation than a flock <strong>of</strong> sheep. 9 But in that case what is a<br />

block <strong>of</strong> marble an aggregate <strong>of</strong>? At first sight it seems that Leibniz would say that<br />

a block <strong>of</strong> marble is an aggregate <strong>of</strong> physical parts which are themselves aggregates<br />

and so on ad infinitum. But though he shows some hesitancy on this issue, in the<br />

correspondence with Arnauld Leibniz suggests that a marble slab is an aggregate<br />

<strong>of</strong> organisms no less than a flock <strong>of</strong> sheep: ‘perhaps this marble block is merely a<br />

heap <strong>of</strong> an infinite number <strong>of</strong> living bodies, or is like a lake full <strong>of</strong> fish, although<br />

these animals are ordinarily visible only in half-rotten bodies.’ 10 This thesis draws<br />

support from the empirical discoveries made possible by the recent invention <strong>of</strong><br />

the microscope.<br />

Thus Leibniz reaches an important negative conclusion which is in obvious<br />

conflict with Cartesian theses; no non-organic bodies are substances. 11 But this<br />

conclusion still leaves open the question <strong>of</strong> Leibniz’s positive views on the issue<br />

<strong>of</strong> what items qualify as substances. Recent work has shown that around the time<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Discourse on Metaphysics Leibniz was remarkably hesitant on this issue;<br />

indeed, he flirted with a number <strong>of</strong> possible positions. 12 He was perhaps<br />

particularly uncertain as to whether anything physical counted as a substance,<br />

but as we shall see, he also had doubts about the ontological status <strong>of</strong> souls.<br />

Despite his hesitations, the view to which he seems to have been most attracted<br />

is that organisms, and perhaps souls, are the only substances; organisms are what<br />

Leibniz calls ‘corporeal substances’. With regard to physical objects, then,<br />

Leibniz’s teaching is that every body is either itself a corporeal substance or an<br />

aggregate <strong>of</strong> corporeal substances.<br />

Leibniz’s somewhat tentative positive thesis raises an obvious question: why are<br />

organisms better candidates for substantiality than non-organic bodies? Leibniz’s<br />

short answer to this question is clear: organisms are not just aggregates but true<br />

unities, and every entity which is endowed with a true unity is a substance. For<br />

Leibniz, an organism is truly one by virtue <strong>of</strong> possessing a soul or principle <strong>of</strong><br />

life which confers unity on it; in scholastic terminology the soul is said to inform<br />

the body. Indeed, Leibniz even goes so far as to revive the scholastic doctrine<br />

that the soul is the substantial form <strong>of</strong> the body; here he is drawing on the fact<br />

that in medieval philosophy it is the presence <strong>of</strong> a substantial form that makes a<br />

body a natural unity. 13

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!