27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

160 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

These considerations are certainly not the only ones, but they are enough to<br />

make us question the received view. Before we can provide an alternative<br />

reading, however, it will be helpful if we can get a better idea <strong>of</strong> what exactly<br />

Descartes is rejecting in traditional accounts <strong>of</strong> method, and what kind <strong>of</strong> thing<br />

he is seeking to achieve in his scientific writings.<br />

THE REJECTION OF ARISTOTELIAN METHOD<br />

Aristotelian syllogistic was widely criticized from the mid-sixteenth century<br />

onwards, and by the middle <strong>of</strong> the seventeenth century had been completely<br />

discredited as a method <strong>of</strong> discovery. This was due more to a misunderstanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the nature and role <strong>of</strong> the syllogism, however, than to any compelling criticism<br />

<strong>of</strong> syllogistic.<br />

Aristotle had presented scientific demonstrations syllogistically, and he had<br />

argued that some forms <strong>of</strong> demonstration provide explanations or causes whereas<br />

others do not. This may occur even where the syllogisms are formally identical.<br />

Consider, for example, the following two syllogisms:<br />

The planets do not twinkle<br />

That which does not twinkle is near<br />

The planets are near<br />

The planets are near<br />

That which is near does not twinkle<br />

The planets do not twinkle<br />

In Aristotle’s discussion <strong>of</strong> these syllogisms in his Posterior Analytics (A17), he<br />

argues that the first is only a demonstration ‘<strong>of</strong> fact’, whereas the second is a<br />

demonstration <strong>of</strong> ‘why’ or a scientific explanation. In the latter we are provided<br />

with a reason or cause or explanation <strong>of</strong> the conclusion: the reason why the<br />

planets do not twinkle is that they are near. In the former, we have a valid but not<br />

a demonstrative argument, since the planets’ not twinkling is hardly a cause or<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong> their being near. So the first syllogism is in some way<br />

uninformative compared with the second: the latter produces understanding, the<br />

former does not. Now Aristotle had great difficulty in providing a convincing<br />

account <strong>of</strong> what exactly it is that distinguishes the first from the second syllogism,<br />

but what he was trying to achieve is clear enough. He was seeking some way <strong>of</strong><br />

identifying those forms <strong>of</strong> deductive inference that resulted in epistemic<br />

advance, that advanced one’s understanding. Realizing that no purely logical<br />

criterion would suffice, he attempted to show that epistemic advance depended<br />

on some non-logical but nevertheless internal or structural feature which some<br />

deductive inferences possess. This question <strong>of</strong> the epistemic value <strong>of</strong> deductive<br />

inferences is one we shall return to, as it underlies the whole problem <strong>of</strong> method.<br />

For Aristotle, the epistemic and the consequential directions in demonstrative<br />

syllogisms run in opposite directions. That is, it is knowing the premises from

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!