27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

374 LEIBNIZ: TRUTH, KNOWLEDGE AND METAPHYSICS<br />

philosophy, that the mind is a naturally immortal, immaterial substance. But<br />

these very differences suggest a way <strong>of</strong> viewing Leibniz’s project, at least with<br />

regard to the mind-body problem; he is seeking to do justice to some <strong>of</strong><br />

Spinoza’s key ideas within the framework <strong>of</strong> traditional Christian theology.<br />

There is indeed much that is Spinozistic in Leibniz’s psychology. Consider,<br />

for instance, how Leibniz applies his concept <strong>of</strong> expression to the relationship<br />

between mind and body. According to Leibniz, the mind does not interact with<br />

the body, but it expresses it in the technical sense <strong>of</strong> the term which he explained<br />

for Arnauld’s benefit. Indeed, Leibniz tells Arnauld that the mind expresses its<br />

own body better than it expresses anything else in the universe. 75 In response to<br />

Arnauld’s query Leibniz explains that he does not mean by this that our mind has<br />

clearer thoughts <strong>of</strong>, say, the activity <strong>of</strong> its lymphatic glands than <strong>of</strong> the satellites<br />

<strong>of</strong> Jupiter; he means rather that given a complete knowledge <strong>of</strong> my mental states<br />

a supermind would find it easier to read <strong>of</strong>f truths about my physical states than<br />

about the celestial bodies. 76 As Spinoza wrote, ‘the ideas that we have <strong>of</strong><br />

external bodies indicate the constitution <strong>of</strong> our own body more than the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

external bodies’. 77 Leibniz might have stopped at this point, but in fact he goes<br />

further; he claims that the mind expresses its body by perceiving it, perception<br />

being a species <strong>of</strong> expression; indeed the mind perceives everything that happens<br />

in its body. 78 Here again Leibniz seems to be following in Spinoza’s footsteps,<br />

for Spinoza had similarly written that ‘whatever happens in the object [i.e. the<br />

body] <strong>of</strong> the idea constituting the human mind is bound to be perceived by the<br />

human mind’. 79 But whereas Spinoza does little to dispel the mystery<br />

surrounding this claim, Leibniz <strong>of</strong>fers a body <strong>of</strong> theory which plugs the gaps in<br />

Spinoza’s account. This is the famous doctrine <strong>of</strong> unconscious perceptions.<br />

Here it is helpful to recall Leibniz’s hierarchical arrangement <strong>of</strong> monads. All<br />

monads perceive, but they differ vastly in terms <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> their<br />

perceptions. Human minds or spirits are distinguished not only by reason but also<br />

by ‘apperception’ which means consciousness or perhaps even selfconsciousness.<br />

But though Leibniz holds that human minds are set apart from<br />

lower monads by their capacity for (self)-conscious awareness, he further<br />

believes that they also have unconscious or little perceptions (petites<br />

perceptions); such perceptions are little because they are low in intensity. Not<br />

merely do large stretches <strong>of</strong> our mental life consist wholly in little perceptions,<br />

but even conscious mental states are composed <strong>of</strong> such perceptions. The doctrine<br />

<strong>of</strong> unconscious perceptions is perhaps Leibniz’s principal innovation in<br />

psychology, and it is <strong>of</strong> course pr<strong>of</strong>oundly anti-Cartesian in its implications. For<br />

Descartes subscribes to the view that the mind is transparent to itself; he is<br />

explicit that there is nothing in the mind <strong>of</strong> which we are not conscious. 80<br />

In the New Essays on Human Understanding, his reply to Locke, Leibniz<br />

remarks that there are ‘thousands <strong>of</strong> indications’ in favour <strong>of</strong> unconscious<br />

perceptions. 81 Obviously there is an element <strong>of</strong> hyperbole in this claim, but even<br />

so, Leibniz certainly has a battery <strong>of</strong> arguments for his doctrine. Some <strong>of</strong> these<br />

arguments are based on a priori principles such as the identity <strong>of</strong> indiscernibles

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!