27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

298 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

But this cannot be all there is to teleology. However much we might realize<br />

that causality is behind our conviction <strong>of</strong> goal-oriented behaviour, this does not<br />

provide us as such with a better understanding <strong>of</strong> our own behaviour. Why do we<br />

strive to realize certain things, and try to escape others? What should we strive<br />

for, and why? To answer these questions we need a more precise understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> what a causal explanation <strong>of</strong> human behaviour amounts to. Burgersdijk and<br />

his school regarded affects as modifications <strong>of</strong> sensitive appetite caused by nonnatural<br />

causes. Affects are in a way the movement <strong>of</strong> this sensitive appetite,<br />

implying that affects are the prerequisite <strong>of</strong> any actual appetite, as appetite is the<br />

prerequisite <strong>of</strong> actual behaviour. This position entailed furthermore that each<br />

affect, being a motivation <strong>of</strong> behaviour, necessarily contains both bodily and<br />

rational elements. And lastly, they asserted affects to be passions, as far as they did<br />

not concur with the judgement <strong>of</strong> practical reason, and to be actions as far as they<br />

did concur. The ultimate end <strong>of</strong> ethics is then to let the affects be in concurrence<br />

with practical reason, and thereby directed at beatitude, that is, the good life.<br />

Ethics is for them the desire for the good life, or eudaimonia.<br />

With this Neostoic, naturalistic ‘theory <strong>of</strong> behaviour’, Spinoza seems to have<br />

less difficulty than with teleology. Indeed, we find in Spinoza a theory <strong>of</strong> affects,<br />

<strong>of</strong> appetite and desire. The Neostoic principle <strong>of</strong> self-preservation surfaces in the<br />

conatus, the conscious striving <strong>of</strong> each thing to persevere in its being (E III P9).<br />

We cannot overlook the role <strong>of</strong> the active-passive distinction in Spinoza, nor the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the body for the conception <strong>of</strong> action. ‘A great many things<br />

happen from the laws <strong>of</strong> nature alone’, that is, from the nature <strong>of</strong> the body,<br />

Spinoza emphasizes in E III P2S where he explains the relative autonomy <strong>of</strong><br />

body and mind. Furthermore, Spinoza’s conception <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> passion to<br />

action shares a conviction with Neostoicism: passive affects are not to be<br />

suppressed, but can proceed by natural force to become active. That education<br />

should not be practised by force or punishment, but by admonition and example,<br />

is a point <strong>of</strong> view that is a complement to this notion <strong>of</strong> passion.<br />

But it is precisely against this background <strong>of</strong> shared ideas that in Spinoza’s<br />

philosophical system no function is left for teleology. In this, he is drawing the<br />

naturalism <strong>of</strong> his predecessors to its full conclusion. The projection onto Nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> man’s self-experienced goal-directedness is not a sign <strong>of</strong> action but <strong>of</strong><br />

passion. Activity is living according to one’s own nature, i.e. according to one’s<br />

being as a particle in Nature, instead <strong>of</strong> (passion driven) believing oneself to be<br />

Nature’s master.<br />

What was at issue in the debate on teleology was (and is) the formulation <strong>of</strong><br />

practical rules for actual behaviour in the perspective <strong>of</strong> an ultimate goal. As it is<br />

presumably God’s end for mankind to realize X, man has a duty to act so as to<br />

further X. Velthuysen amends this: God’s end is X, man is provided with means<br />

M, so employing M will by God’s provident ordering <strong>of</strong> Nature to further X. In<br />

this version M provides in a derivative fashion the criteria for our practical<br />

behaviour. One <strong>of</strong> Velthuysen’s main criteria is the ‘fundamental law <strong>of</strong> selfpreservation’.<br />

However, Velthuysen had to accept that M is necessary but not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!