27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM 365<br />

according to Leibniz, there is only one kind <strong>of</strong> basic entities, namely souls. In<br />

this respect the contrast with Spinoza’s monism is at a maximum. Far from<br />

asserting that there is just one substance, Leibniz holds that there are infinitely<br />

many simple substances and that, by virtue <strong>of</strong> the identity <strong>of</strong> indiscernibles, no<br />

two are exactly alike.<br />

Monads are in fact hierarchically arranged. At the top <strong>of</strong> the hierarchy is God<br />

who seems to be the supreme monad; 45 at the bottom <strong>of</strong> the hierarchy are what<br />

Leibniz calls ‘bare monads’ which provide the metaphysical foundation for<br />

inanimate matter. The basis for this hierarchical classification is quality <strong>of</strong><br />

perception; borrowing Cartesian terminology, Leibniz says that monads differ in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the clarity and distinctness <strong>of</strong> their perceptions. For example, the minds<br />

<strong>of</strong> human beings are near the top <strong>of</strong> the hierarchy by virtue <strong>of</strong> their capacity for a<br />

very high grade <strong>of</strong> perception, namely reason. A striking feature <strong>of</strong> monadology,<br />

however, is that although monads differ enormously in terms <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong><br />

perception, in a sense they do not differ in terms <strong>of</strong> the objects they perceive; for<br />

giving a new twist to his expression thesis Leibniz holds that every monad<br />

perceives the whole universe according to its point <strong>of</strong> view. The qualification<br />

tacked on to this thesis is to be understood in terms <strong>of</strong> the doctrine that there are<br />

qualitative differences among perceptions. To say that two monads differ in their<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view is to say that they do not enjoy exactly the same distribution <strong>of</strong><br />

clarity and distinctness over their perceptual states. In this way Leibniz can also<br />

explain how the identity <strong>of</strong> indiscernibles applies to monads in spite <strong>of</strong> the fact<br />

that they all perceive the whole universe.<br />

These are remarkable doctrines, and we may well wonder how Leibniz came<br />

to arrive at them. In fact, however, the basic argument for the fundamental<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> monadology is quite straightforward; it turns on two main<br />

assumptions: the infinite divisibility <strong>of</strong> matter and the thesis that there must be<br />

basic or ultimate entities. For Leibniz, it would be shocking to reason, or at least<br />

to divine wisdom, if everything in the universe were composed <strong>of</strong> compounds<br />

whose components were themselves compounds, and so on ad infinitum. The<br />

infinite divisibility <strong>of</strong> matter implies that these basic entities cannot be physical,<br />

for everything physical is a compound <strong>of</strong> the sort just described. Thus although<br />

physical atoms are a fiction, there can and must be ‘spiritual atoms’ or monads.<br />

A natural initial reaction to monadology is to wonder at Leibniz’s willingness<br />

to prefer it to the more down-to-earth metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Discourse. But in<br />

response to the argument outlined above we may wonder why Leibniz was not in<br />

a position to advance it earlier. Certainly throughout his career Leibniz holds that<br />

the universe must consist <strong>of</strong> basic or ultimate entities. Moreover, in his earlier<br />

philosophy Leibniz also held a version <strong>of</strong> the thesis <strong>of</strong> the infinite divisibility <strong>of</strong><br />

matter; matter, considered in abstraction from souls or substantial forms, is<br />

infinitely divisible ‘in innumerable possible ways but not actually divided in<br />

any’. 46 So at the time <strong>of</strong> writing the Discourse Leibniz believed, as he continued<br />

to believe, that nothing purely material could be a basic entity. But the difference<br />

between Leibniz’s earlier and later views seems to be this. In the Discourse

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!