27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

134 FRANCIS BACON AND MAN’S TWO-FACED KINGDOM<br />

with others conjures up a great panoply <strong>of</strong> illusion and imposture, where truth<br />

succumbs to the sophistries <strong>of</strong> social convention: these are the Idola Theatri or<br />

Idols <strong>of</strong> the Theatre. According to Bacon, there is no thinking in a vacuum: man<br />

is beset by what others thought before him, and therefore he is the appointed heir<br />

to all past sects and philosophies. The Idols <strong>of</strong> the Theatre are for ever hovering<br />

over the prospective philosopher (Nov. Org. I, 44). The mind <strong>of</strong> man, in sum, is<br />

by no means a tabula abrasa, to use the consecrated empiricist shibboleth, but<br />

rather an ‘enchanted glass’ or ‘distorted mirror’ (St Paul, I Cor. 13: 9–10, 12).<br />

The true interpreter <strong>of</strong> Nature, that is, the true philosopher, must be always on his<br />

guard against the intrusion <strong>of</strong> such Trugbilder or mirages into his field <strong>of</strong><br />

cognitive interests. Bacon, however, never expressly states that man can become<br />

entirely free from such deceiving propensities. Not even the last <strong>of</strong> them, that is,<br />

the Idola Theatri or unlawful children <strong>of</strong> philosophy, disappear from the<br />

menacing potential <strong>of</strong> Bacon’s own speculations.<br />

Let us go back to the technocratic component that the concept <strong>of</strong> instauratio<br />

encapsulated. Bacon, seemingly innocently, defines philosophy as ‘the Inquiry <strong>of</strong><br />

Causes and the Production <strong>of</strong> Effects’ (De Augmentis III, 4: I, 550; <strong>IV</strong>, 346).<br />

Likewise, the High Priest in the Nova Atlantis instructs the admiring visitor by<br />

telling him that ‘the end <strong>of</strong> our Foundation [that is, Salomon’s House] is the<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> causes, and secret motions <strong>of</strong> things; and the enlarging <strong>of</strong> the<br />

bounds <strong>of</strong> human empire to the effecting <strong>of</strong> all things possible’ (III, 156).<br />

Now, the decisively striking point in these and similar definitions is their second<br />

part, for traditional philosophical discourse did not contemplate the physical<br />

production <strong>of</strong> anything. Surely, the ‘effects’ (opera) to be achieved are dictated<br />

by the general philanthropic tenor <strong>of</strong> Bacon’s philosophy, but it would be a gross<br />

mistake to confuse it, as is <strong>of</strong>ten done, with any form <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism. 19 First <strong>of</strong><br />

all, we have to identify the ideological trend that Bacon is recapturing when<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>fering such pithy definitions. Now, this trend leads us back to a tradition<br />

which, though prior to humanistic thought, inspired a great deal <strong>of</strong> philosophical<br />

writing in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. In fact, the first great<br />

representative <strong>of</strong> this current in the modern epoch is Nicholas <strong>of</strong> Cusa (1401–<br />

64), who systematically reflected on the much-discussed relationship between<br />

God’s and man’s intellect and their opera. Heir to Neoplatonic traditions, Cusa<br />

establishes that man, that fallen creature, is not wholly devoid <strong>of</strong> that allimportant<br />

and defining attribute <strong>of</strong> the Christian Godhead: the power to create. 20<br />

Even as God created the world, man is empowered to create another world (that<br />

<strong>of</strong> mathematicals and abstract notions) in so far as he is not eternally condemned<br />

to copying or imitating Nature but is able to surpass her by making items (e.g. a<br />

spoon) for which Nature has no exemplar or prototype. 21 Of course, Cusa’s main<br />

interests were theological and hence he did not develop a line <strong>of</strong> thought which<br />

we could easily link with ‘the question <strong>of</strong> technology’, as it came to be<br />

formulated much later. But it is surprising how tantalizingly close he came to<br />

giving a systematic response to many <strong>of</strong> the sporadic pronouncements—

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!