27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPINOZA: METAPHYSICS AND KNOWLEDGE 265<br />

and thinking substance, he implied that each has many attributes (Principles <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Philosophy</strong>, Pt I, 53; CSM i, 210), understanding by an attribute (ibid., Pt I, 56)<br />

that which always remains unmodified, such as existence and duration in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> created things. Each substance, however, has one ‘principal attribute’,<br />

and these are extension in the case <strong>of</strong> corporeal substance and thought in the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking substance. Spinoza and Descartes, then, agree in holding that one<br />

must explain physical nature in terms <strong>of</strong> extension and mental states and events<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> thought. They also agree to some extent (though here there are also<br />

important differences) that we must explain the former in terms <strong>of</strong> extension<br />

alone and the latter in terms <strong>of</strong> thought alone. Descartes expresses this by saying<br />

(Meditation VI, CSM ii, 54) that corporeal and thinking substance are ‘really<br />

distinct’. 53 Spinoza would say that Descartes was right in holding that we cannot<br />

mix mental terms with physical terms when we try to explain either mind or<br />

matter—still less can we reduce mental terms to physical terms (as in the case <strong>of</strong><br />

materialism) or physical terms to mental terms. But, he would say, the<br />

metaphysics in terms <strong>of</strong> which Descartes made this point was seriously at fault.<br />

Contrary to Descartes, there is only one substance, and what Descartes says in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> two substances must be translated into terms <strong>of</strong> the attributes <strong>of</strong> thought<br />

and extension, each <strong>of</strong> which is ‘conceived through itself’. 54<br />

Spinoza would also argue that by regarding thought and extension in this way<br />

—as self-enclosed attributes, which are attributes <strong>of</strong> one substance—he can solve<br />

a problem which had faced Descartes: that <strong>of</strong> the relation between mind and<br />

body. Descartes wanted to maintain two theses: first, that corporeal and mental<br />

substance are really distinct, but second, that mind and body act on each other,<br />

and indeed that the human being is a unity <strong>of</strong> mind and body. The problem for<br />

Descartes was to explain how these propositions can both be true, and Spinoza<br />

thought (as many others have thought) that he failed to do so. To grasp Spinoza’s<br />

solution, however, it is necessary to go further into his system. This is because the<br />

problem is one which concerns particular minds and particular bodies, and this<br />

means that one has to see how Spinoza accommodates these within his system.<br />

That is, it is necessary to consider his theory <strong>of</strong> ‘modes’.<br />

Spinoza argues, not only that the infinite substance must be unique, but that it<br />

must also be indivisible, and that the same can be said <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> its attributes. 55<br />

This raises the question <strong>of</strong> how the indivisible substance, or its indivisible<br />

attributes, is to be related to the particular things that we meet in our experience.<br />

That is, it raises the question: what is the place <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> a particular<br />

thing in Spinoza’s system? The answer is that it enters by way <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘mode’. Particular things, Spinoza says, are simply ‘modes by which attributes <strong>of</strong><br />

God are expressed in a certain and determinate manner’. 56 Spinoza has already<br />

defined a mode in the fifth <strong>of</strong> the definitions <strong>of</strong> Part I <strong>of</strong> the Ethics, saying that it<br />

is ‘that which is in something else, through which it is also conceived’. This<br />

definition can be illuminated by relating it to what Descartes has to say about<br />

real and modal distinctions. For Descartes, a real distinction holds between two<br />

or more substances, and is recognized by the fact that one can be clearly and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!