27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM 359<br />

deduction is watertight; at points Leibniz seems to be smuggling in certain<br />

unstated non-logical premises.<br />

The claim that Leibniz derived his metaphysics from his logic is more<br />

mysterious than it need be. When Russell and Couturat put forward this thesis,<br />

they had something quite specific in mind when they spoke <strong>of</strong> Leibniz’s ‘logic’:<br />

they were referring to his theory <strong>of</strong> truth. The theory <strong>of</strong> truth in question is<br />

explicitly stated, not in the Discourse on Metaphysics, but in the correspondence<br />

with Arnauld where it appears almost as an afterthought. However, the theory<br />

makes itself felt in the Discourse, for it seems to ground the deep analysis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> substance which Leibniz <strong>of</strong>fers as a supplement to Aristotle.<br />

Leibniz’s distinctive theory <strong>of</strong> truth can best be explained by way <strong>of</strong> contrast.<br />

Perhaps the most intuitive doctrine <strong>of</strong> truth is some version <strong>of</strong> the<br />

correspondence theory; in other words, truth consists in a relation <strong>of</strong><br />

correspondence between propositions and states <strong>of</strong> affairs in the world. It is some<br />

version <strong>of</strong> the correspondence theory that Aristotle seems to have had in mind<br />

when he defined truth as saying <strong>of</strong> that which is that it is and <strong>of</strong> that which is not<br />

that it is not. 23 Although he sometimes seems to suggest that he is simply<br />

following in Aristotle’s footsteps, Leibniz in fact advances a radically different<br />

theory. For Leibniz, truth consists not in a correspondence between propositions<br />

and states <strong>of</strong> affairs but in a relation between concepts. Leibniz provides a<br />

succinct summary <strong>of</strong> his theory in a letter to Arnauld: ‘In every true affirmative<br />

proposition, necessary or contingent, universal or particular, the concept <strong>of</strong> the<br />

predicate is in a sense included in that <strong>of</strong> the subject: praedicatum inest subjecto;<br />

or else I do not know what truth is.’ 24 Let us call this ‘the concept-containment<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> truth’.<br />

Leibniz’s theory <strong>of</strong> truth can be seen as a generalization <strong>of</strong> a more familiar and<br />

more limited claim. Consider the proposition: ‘Gold is a metal’. It is plausible to<br />

say that the proposition is true because the concept expressed by the predicate<br />

term is contained in the concept expressed by the subject term; in other words, an<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> gold would reveal that the concept <strong>of</strong> metal is one <strong>of</strong><br />

its constituent concepts. (Analysis is conceived <strong>of</strong> here as a matter <strong>of</strong> replacing a<br />

given term by its definitional equivalent.) As his comment to Arnauld shows,<br />

Leibniz wishes to extend this insight to all affirmative propositions, including<br />

singular ones such as ‘Julius Caesar crossed the Rubicon’. Thus Leibniz holds<br />

that the proper name ‘Julius Caesar’ is not simply an arbitrary label; it expresses<br />

a concept no less than the term ‘gold’ does. The proposition ‘Julius Caesar<br />

crossed the Rubicon’ is true because the concept <strong>of</strong> crossing the Rubicon is<br />

contained in the concept <strong>of</strong> Julius Caesar. From this general, conceptcontainment<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> truth Leibniz’s distinctive claim about the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

individual substances follows as a special case; by virtue <strong>of</strong> the general theory,<br />

all the predicates which are true <strong>of</strong> an individual substance are contained in the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> that substance. 25<br />

‘From these considerations there follow a number <strong>of</strong> important paradoxes.’ 26<br />

This remark in the Discourse is key evidence for the claim that Leibniz derived his

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!