27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

with each other than with the respects in which they agreed; so, for example,<br />

Spinoza criticized Descartes, Malebranche criticized Spinoza, and Leibniz<br />

criticized Descartes, Spinoza and Malebranche. Again, those who regard these<br />

philosophers as a group <strong>of</strong>ten contrast them with the ‘British empiricists’,<br />

namely Locke, Berkeley and Hume. Yet Locke’s use <strong>of</strong> the important term ‘idea’<br />

owed something to Descartes, and Malebranche influenced both Berkeley and<br />

Hume. Despite all this, the philosophers who are commonly called the<br />

seventeenth-century rationalists did have a number <strong>of</strong> basic views in common.<br />

All agreed that it is possible to get to know the nature <strong>of</strong> reality simply by means<br />

<strong>of</strong> a priori reasoning; that is, that we can get to know by means <strong>of</strong> the reason,<br />

without any appeal to the senses, truths about reality that are necessary truths. It<br />

is these points <strong>of</strong> resemblance, above all, that the term ‘rationalist’ picks out. In<br />

this sense, rationalism is not peculiar to the seventeenth century; the ‘dialectic’<br />

that is described in Plato’s Republic (510–11, 532–4) is a rationalist theory. Nor<br />

did rationalism come to an end after the death <strong>of</strong> Leibniz. It continued to exist,<br />

not just in the writings <strong>of</strong> Leibniz’s follower Christian Wolff, but also in the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘objective idealism’ <strong>of</strong> Hegel, and perhaps even after that. 27 Our concern,<br />

however, is with its seventeenth-century manifestations.<br />

The time-span <strong>of</strong> the movement is well enough indicated by the name given to<br />

it. Its first public manifestation was in Descartes’s Discourse on Method,<br />

published in 1637; it ended in 1716, the year in which Leibniz—still<br />

philosophically active—died. Though not as widespread as the Renaissance, it<br />

was by no means confined to one country. Descartes worked in France and the<br />

Netherlands; Malebranche worked in France; Geulincx and Spinoza worked in<br />

the Low Countries, and Leibniz worked mainly in Germany (though one should<br />

not overlook a very productive period which he spent in Paris between 1672 and<br />

1676). Seventeenth-century rationalism also spanned the religions. Descartes and<br />

Malebranche were Roman Catholics (Malebranche, indeed, was a priest);<br />

Geulincx was initially a Catholic but became a convert to Protestantism after<br />

being persecuted for Cartesian views; Spinoza was an excommunicated Jew,<br />

with friends among some <strong>of</strong> the smaller Protestant sects.<br />

Like Bacon, the rationalists saw themselves as making a new start. Most <strong>of</strong><br />

them were contemptuous <strong>of</strong> Aristotle and the scholastics; 28 indeed, they rejected<br />

everything that passed for received wisdom in their time, as long as it did not<br />

meet the demands <strong>of</strong> rational scrutiny. This is very clearly expressed in<br />

Descartes’s resolve, stated in the first part <strong>of</strong> his Meditations, 29 ‘to demolish<br />

everything completely and start again right from the foundations’. But no one<br />

philosophizes in an intellectual vacuum, and it is important to note that the rise<br />

<strong>of</strong> rationalism in the seventeenth century occurred at the same time as, and was<br />

closely associated with, the rise <strong>of</strong> what one now calls ‘modern science’. The<br />

new science is discussed at length in Chapter 3 <strong>of</strong> this volume; here it must be<br />

sufficient to say that the old and largely Aristotelian science stressed the<br />

qualitative aspect <strong>of</strong> nature, and was primarily concerned to classify, whereas the<br />

new science stressed the quantitative aspect <strong>of</strong> things, <strong>of</strong>fering explanations that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!