27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

182 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

17 On this question see M.Gueroult, ‘The Metaphysics and Physics <strong>of</strong> Force in<br />

Descartes’, and A.Gabbey, ‘Force and Inertia in the Seventeenth Century:<br />

Descartes and Newton’, both in [5.27], 196–229 and 230–320 respectively.<br />

18 See, for example, his reply to Henry More’s objection that modes are not alienable<br />

in [5.1], vol. 5, 403–4.<br />

19 [5.1], vol. 7, 108; [5.5], vol. 2, 78.<br />

20 See Wahl [5.73].<br />

21 For details <strong>of</strong> this issue see Stephen Gaukroger, Explanatory Structures: Concepts<br />

<strong>of</strong> Explanation in Early Physics and <strong>Philosophy</strong> (Brighton, Harvester, 1978), ch. 6.<br />

22 For details see Jean-Paul Weber, La Constitution du texte des Regulae (Paris,<br />

1964).<br />

23 [5.1], vol. 10, 377–8; [5.5], vol. 1, 19.<br />

24 See John Schuster, ‘Descartes’ Mathesis Universalis 1619–28’, in [5.27], 41–96.<br />

25 [5.1], vol. 6, 63–5.<br />

26 [5.1], vol. 1, 559–60.<br />

27 [5.1], vol. 5, 325.<br />

28 [5.1], vol. 6, 326–7.<br />

29 [5.1], vol. 6, 336.<br />

30 See the discussion in Beck [5.39], 176ff.<br />

31 Rule 4, [5.1], vol. 10, 276–7; [5.1], vol. 5, 19.<br />

32 [5.1], vol. 10, 455–6, 458.<br />

33 On the authors whom Descartes would have studied at his college, La Flèche, see<br />

Gilson [5.20]. On the textbook tradition more generally, see Patricia Reif, ‘The<br />

Textbook Tradition in Natural <strong>Philosophy</strong>, 1600–1650’, Journal <strong>of</strong> the <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

Ideas 30 (1969) 17–32.<br />

34 It is rare to find anyone who not only takes the deductive approach at face value<br />

and also believes it is viable, but there is at least one notable example <strong>of</strong> such an<br />

interpretation, namely Spinoza’s Principles <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Philosophy</strong> <strong>of</strong> René Descartes<br />

(1663).<br />

35 [5–1], vol. 6, 18–19; [5.5], vol. 1, 120.<br />

36 See, for example, Leibniz’s letter to Gabriel Wagner <strong>of</strong> 1696, in C.I.Gerhardt (ed.)<br />

Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (Berlin, Weidman,<br />

1875–90), vol. 7, 514–27, especially Comment 3 on p. 523. The letter is translated<br />

in L.E.Loemker, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters<br />

(Dordrecht, Reidel, 1969), pp. 462–71, with Comment 3 on p. 468.<br />

37 Adrianus Turnebus (1512–65) was Royal Reader in Greek at the Collège de<br />

France. He was one <strong>of</strong> the leading humanist translators <strong>of</strong> his day, and had an<br />

extensive knowledge <strong>of</strong> Greek philosophy.<br />

38 [5.1], vol. 10, 372; [5.5], vol. 1, 16.<br />

39 [5.1], vol. 10, 387–8; [5.5], vol. 1, 25.<br />

40 [5.1], vol. 10, 439–40; [5–5], vol. 1, 57.<br />

41 M.Dummett, ‘The Justification <strong>of</strong> Deduction’, in his Truth and Other Enigmas<br />

(London, Duckworth, 1978), p. 296.<br />

42 On this influence see, specifically in the case <strong>of</strong> Locke, J.Passmore, ‘Descartes, the<br />

British Empiricists and Formal Logic’, Philosophical Review 62 (1953), 545–53;<br />

and more generally, W.S.Howell, Eighteenth-Century British Logic and Rhetoric<br />

(Princeton, N.J., Princeton University Press, 1971).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!