27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA 315<br />

In the Latin <strong>of</strong> Spinoza we find that the multitude ‘ex communi aliquo affectu<br />

naturaliter convenire’, that is, ‘from some shared emotion agree by nature’.<br />

‘Agreement’ being a somewhat more precise translation than Elwes’s ‘coming<br />

together’, we find here the principle <strong>of</strong> co-operation explained that we had been<br />

looking for in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. In the shared or common<br />

emotion we see the civil state arise. What kind <strong>of</strong> emotion is Spinoza thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong>? In TP III, 6, he points to the removal <strong>of</strong> general fear and the prevention <strong>of</strong><br />

general sufferings as a natural cause <strong>of</strong> the state. These ‘communes miserias’<br />

seem to refer to the emotion <strong>of</strong> misericordia, compassion. We find it again in TP<br />

I, 5, together with jealousy or envy, vengeance, and ambition and glory. These<br />

passions predominate in an ordinary man, especially since men are led more by<br />

passion than by reason. Anyone who thinks otherwise believes in a chimera or in<br />

a Utopia, or in the golden age <strong>of</strong> the poets (TP I, 1). It is clear, however, that we<br />

need something more than just these passions. Thomas Hobbes would explain<br />

the war <strong>of</strong> all men against all men from these passions. How can Spinoza come<br />

to the explanation <strong>of</strong> the state? We have to take a close look at the term<br />

‘convenire’, agree.<br />

We will then be dealing with the pre-political, state, that is, as long as the<br />

condition is not realized ‘that all, governing and governed alike, whether they<br />

will or no, shall do what makes for the general welfare: that is, that all, whether<br />

<strong>of</strong> their own impulse, or by force or necessity, shall be compelled to live<br />

according to the dictate <strong>of</strong> reason’ (TP VI, 3). As long as this condition is not<br />

realized, any order that may arise is not stable. People may agree for a moment,<br />

but disintegrate in the next. How can such an unstable agreement develop into a<br />

stable one? This may happen if such a temporary agreement induces people to<br />

agree on further points, leading to patterns <strong>of</strong> behaviour, habits and preferences<br />

that can be redefined as a political order. Spinoza seems to suggest this much<br />

when he says that compassion can induce men to alleviate the misery <strong>of</strong> others,<br />

from ambition or love <strong>of</strong> glory. Such ambitious men may want to continue to<br />

attract the praise <strong>of</strong> others, because they see it as a consequence <strong>of</strong> their help.<br />

Others may want the same, and thereby ambition becomes a motive for political<br />

leadership. Now, jealousy could follow if there is not room enough for all<br />

ambitious men, and fear and hate might follow as well. In that case, the evolution<br />

is thwarted. But if the surrounding world poses enough challenges, the effects<br />

may well be positive. Then, ‘love <strong>of</strong> liberty, desire to increase their property, and<br />

hope <strong>of</strong> gaining the honours <strong>of</strong> dominion’ (TP X, 8) will be the sure emotions<br />

leading to a stable political order. Interdependence <strong>of</strong> emotions makes for<br />

political order, but this process may equally well degenerate according to the<br />

circumstances.<br />

This dual character <strong>of</strong> emotive interdependence provides a good explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Spinoza’s use <strong>of</strong> positive and negative examples <strong>of</strong> political order. Positive<br />

examples (the kingdom <strong>of</strong> Aragon, the Dutch Republic) are indicative <strong>of</strong> the<br />

necessary conditions for their respective forms <strong>of</strong> government; negative<br />

examples (the Jewish state, Rome, France, Venice) show disturbing factors. On

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!