27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

234 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

Ethics and politics<br />

In his physics Gassendi departs considerably from Epicurus but retains a version<br />

<strong>of</strong> atomism and a largely materialistic account <strong>of</strong> the biological soul. 8 The effect<br />

<strong>of</strong> the departures is to make the Epicurean doctrine cohere with Christianity. God<br />

is brought in not only as creator but as a maintainer <strong>of</strong> order in material<br />

causation: the combination <strong>of</strong> atoms by chance is outlawed. God is also brought<br />

in as immediate source <strong>of</strong> a higher immaterial soul. Epicurean physics is<br />

corrected by theology, and it is the same with Epicurean ethics, which Gassendi<br />

takes up in the third and concluding part <strong>of</strong> the Syntagma. 9<br />

Epicurus is upheld in claiming that pleasure is to be pursued and pain avoided,<br />

but the pleasure <strong>of</strong> certain types <strong>of</strong> action is interpreted by Gassendi as a divinely<br />

appointed sign <strong>of</strong> the individual or communal preservation that such actions<br />

promote, while the pain <strong>of</strong> other types <strong>of</strong> action must be seen as a sign <strong>of</strong> their<br />

interfering with conservation (Op. Omn., 701). There are pleasures <strong>of</strong> motion and<br />

pleasures <strong>of</strong> rest, and Epicurus was right, according to Gassendi, to associate<br />

happiness with enjoyment <strong>of</strong> the pleasures <strong>of</strong> rest. He was right, in other words,<br />

to prefer the quiet pleasures <strong>of</strong> the mind to the pleasures <strong>of</strong> eating, drinking and<br />

sex. The fact that it does not come naturally to us to give the quiet pleasures their<br />

due; the fact that we are inclined to pursue the earthier pleasures to the exclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the others; these facts do not show that happiness is beyond us. They only<br />

show that happiness is not automatically attained. Fortunately, however, we are<br />

blessed by God with a freedom that, if properly used, enables us to judge that the<br />

earthier pleasures are not superior and are even at times merely apparent rather<br />

than real pleasures. This power <strong>of</strong> correcting valuations through judgement does<br />

not deprive the lower pleasures <strong>of</strong> their attraction, or bring it about that there is<br />

nothing to disturb us once we have chosen the higher goods. In other words, our<br />

freedom cannot bring about happiness in the form <strong>of</strong> perfect freedom from<br />

perturbation; on the other hand, it does make choices <strong>of</strong> the higher pleasures into<br />

genuine choices. Someone whose valuations <strong>of</strong> pleasure were completely correct<br />

morally speaking and who was incapable <strong>of</strong> making the wrong choices would in<br />

a certain sense resemble creatures who acted badly under the influence <strong>of</strong><br />

impulse, for they, like the unfailingly right-acting, act in the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

spontaneity (Op. Omn. II, 822–3).<br />

Going by the theological corrections one finds elsewhere in his system, one<br />

might expect Gassendi to make Epicurean tranquillity consist <strong>of</strong> the quiet<br />

contemplation <strong>of</strong> God in a place away from the distracting pressures <strong>of</strong> social<br />

life. This would fit in not only with the demands <strong>of</strong> piety but with Epicurus’s<br />

endorsement <strong>of</strong> the life in retirement. But in fact the pleasant life appears to be<br />

both more active and more social than this (Op. Omn. II, 717, 720). For<br />

Gassendi, the preferred sort <strong>of</strong> tranquillity appears to be that <strong>of</strong> the man who<br />

quietly and calmly gets on with large undertakings (ibid., 717), rather than<br />

someone who withdraws into serene and solitary meditation. Of course, it is<br />

possible to get on quietly and calmly with purely self-interested projects, such as

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!