27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SPINOZA: METAPHYSICS AND KNOWLEDGE 273<br />

inferred from these. Such a position is consistent with the supposition that there<br />

could have been other laws, or that the initial state <strong>of</strong> the universe could have<br />

been different. For Spinoza, on the other hand, both the laws and the initial state<br />

are necessary, in the sense that no others are strictly speaking thinkable.<br />

Spinoza’s chief concern in the Ethics is with the human being, and more<br />

specifically with the human mind. It has already been seen that Spinoza, contrary<br />

to Descartes, argues that the human mind is not a substance; on the positive side<br />

he argues that, just as the human body is something highly complex, so also is<br />

the human mind. More precisely, the human mind is an idea which is composed<br />

<strong>of</strong> many ideas (Ethics, Pt II, Proposition 15). Spinoza’s account <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

mind is much more elaborate than his account <strong>of</strong> the human body, and falls into<br />

two main sections. The first <strong>of</strong> these, which occupies much <strong>of</strong> Part II <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Ethics, concerns topics which belong to the theory <strong>of</strong> knowledge—namely, the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> a true idea, and <strong>of</strong> the kinds <strong>of</strong> knowledge. The second section, which<br />

begins in the course <strong>of</strong> Part III, concerns the human mind as something which is<br />

appetitive and has emotions. Our primary concern in this chapter is with the<br />

topics that belong to the theory <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

Spinoza speaks both <strong>of</strong> ‘true ideas’ and ‘adequate ideas’; these are closely<br />

related. He says <strong>of</strong> a true idea that it must ‘agree with’ its object; an adequate<br />

idea is a true idea which is as it were abstracted from its relation to its object and<br />

considered only in respect <strong>of</strong> its internal properties. 75 In speaking <strong>of</strong> truth as<br />

‘agreement’, Spinoza might seem to have in mind some version <strong>of</strong> the<br />

correspondence theory <strong>of</strong> truth. It will be recalled that, for Spinoza, to have an<br />

idea involves making a judgement (p. 290); so one might suppose him to mean<br />

that my idea <strong>of</strong> (say) an existent Peter is true when my judgement that Peter<br />

exists corresponds to a certain fact, namely, Peter’s existence. In fact, however,<br />

this is not so; when Spinoza speaks <strong>of</strong> a true idea he is speaking not so much <strong>of</strong><br />

truth as <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

Perhaps the first hint <strong>of</strong> this is given in Proposition 43 <strong>of</strong> Part II <strong>of</strong> the Ethics,<br />

where Spinoza says that ‘He who has a true idea, knows at the same time that he<br />

has a true idea.’ This may seem to be a glaring error; Plato, one may object, was<br />

obviously right when he said (Meno, 97a) that to have a true belief that this is the<br />

road to Larissa is not the same as knowing that this is the road to Larissa.<br />

However, the appearance <strong>of</strong> paradox vanishes when it is realized that Spinoza is<br />

using the term ‘true’ in a special sense. A passage from the early Tractatus de<br />

Intellectus Emendatione is relevant here. Spinoza says (G ii, 26) that<br />

If anyone says that Peter, e.g., exists, but does not know that Peter exists,<br />

his thought is, as far as he is concerned, false— or, if you prefer, is not true<br />

—even though Peter really does exist. The assertion ‘Peter exists’ is true<br />

only with respect to a person who knows for certain that Peter exists. 76<br />

That this was also Spinoza’s view in the Ethics is indicated by the note to<br />

Proposition 43 <strong>of</strong> Part II, which states that to have a true idea is to ‘know

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!