27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

274 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

something perfectly or in the best way’. When Spinoza says in the Ethics,<br />

therefore, that a person who has a true idea knows that he has a true idea, he is<br />

not saying something that is inconsistent with what Plato had said about<br />

knowledge and true belief; what he is saying is that the person who knows, knows<br />

that he knows.<br />

There is more to be said about Spinoza’s views concerning knowledge and<br />

truth. In the note to Proposition 43 <strong>of</strong> Part II <strong>of</strong> the Ethics that has just been<br />

cited, Spinoza says, not just that to have a true idea is to know, but that it is to<br />

know something ‘perfectly or in the best way’ (perfecte sive optime). Here, he is<br />

referring to a point already made in Part II <strong>of</strong> the Ethics (Note 2 to Proposition<br />

40)—namely, that there are various kinds <strong>of</strong> knowledge. 77 Now, from what he<br />

says about these kinds <strong>of</strong> knowledge it emerges that it is possible to have<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> a sort—knowledge which is not perfect—without having a true<br />

idea, in that the idea that one has is only inadequate. The suggestion that one can<br />

know that p, even though the proposition that p is not true, may seem to be yet<br />

another paradox. However, a consideration <strong>of</strong> what Spinoza has to say about the<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> knowledge shows that the paradox is only apparent.<br />

In the note just mentioned, Spinoza says that there are three kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge, which he calls respectively ‘imagination’, ‘reason’ and ‘intuitive<br />

knowledge’. The first <strong>of</strong> these is the one that is relevant to the topic now at issue,<br />

and will concern us in the rest <strong>of</strong> this section. ‘Imagination’ includes particular<br />

propositions that are based on sense experience and general propositions which are<br />

derived by induction from particular instances. 78 Spinoza says that such<br />

knowledge is knowledge from what one may render as ‘uncertain’ or<br />

‘inconstant’ (vaga) experience. By this he means (ibid.) that the ideas involved<br />

are fragmentary and without rational order; he also says that they are ‘inadequate<br />

and confused’ (Proposition 41 <strong>of</strong> Part II). This means, then, that there is a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge—namely, imagination—which involves inadequate or false ideas.<br />

Light is thrown on this by Spinoza’s remark (Ethics, Pt II, Proposition 28) that<br />

confused ideas are ‘like consequences without premises’. What Spinoza means<br />

may be explained as follows. Suppose that I see a certain pen in front <strong>of</strong> me;<br />

suppose, too, that there really is a pen there—i.e. no sense illusion is involved.<br />

Now, my seeing this pen is the result <strong>of</strong> a complex set <strong>of</strong> causes; but in so far as I<br />

merely see the pen, I am unable to trace these causes. That is, I am unable to give<br />

an explanation <strong>of</strong> what it is for me to see this pen. So although I know that there<br />

is a pen there (more <strong>of</strong> this later) I have only an inadequate idea <strong>of</strong> the pen. If I<br />

am to have an adequate idea <strong>of</strong> it, I must make use <strong>of</strong> knowledge which does not<br />

rest on sense experience alone. For example, I must make use <strong>of</strong> physics, to<br />

explain the relation between the pen and my sense organs and brain, and I must also<br />

make use <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, to explain the relation between a corporeal state and<br />

the corresponding idea.<br />

Another sort <strong>of</strong> imagination recognized by Spinoza is knowledge based on<br />

induction. His account <strong>of</strong> this is very brief but appears to proceed along lines that<br />

are similar to his account <strong>of</strong> sense experience. Just as there is knowledge that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!