27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

INTRODUCTION 13<br />

and experience.) Leibniz rejected both these approaches, and argued that scientific<br />

laws have to be seen in relation to the wise and good purposes <strong>of</strong> God.<br />

39 Spinoza argued that human beings have no free will, since everything in the mind<br />

is determined by a cause, and that by another, and so on to infinity (Ethics, Pt II,<br />

Proposition 48). His way <strong>of</strong> reconciling determinism and freedom was to say that<br />

freedom consists, not in an absence <strong>of</strong> determination, but in self-determination.<br />

Such self-determination occurs when the reason controls the passions, which are in<br />

a way outside us. This view—which amounts to saying that to be free is to be<br />

master <strong>of</strong> oneself—is a form <strong>of</strong> what Isaiah Berlin has called the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

‘positive freedom’ (Berlin, ‘Two Concepts <strong>of</strong> Liberty’, Four Essays on Liberty<br />

(Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1969), pp. 118–72). Leibniz, for his part,<br />

discussed both the theological forms <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> freedom and the problems<br />

posed by the thesis that every event is caused. He accepted this thesis, but argued<br />

(contrary to Spinoza) that there is freedom <strong>of</strong> the will. In essence, his argument was<br />

that human actions are indeed necessary, but that they are only hypothetically<br />

necessary. That is, given that X is, at the moment, my strongest motive, then I must<br />

act in accordance with this motive. But I still could have acted otherwise—that is,<br />

my will is free—in that my acting in some other way is always logically possible.<br />

On Spinoza’s views about determinism see (besides Chapter 8, pp. 294–5, and<br />

Chapter 9, pp. 323–6) Jonathan Bennett, A Study <strong>of</strong> Spinoza’s ‘Ethics’ (Cambridge,<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 315–29; R.J.Delahunty, Spinoza (London,<br />

<strong>Routledge</strong>, 1985), pp. 35–48, 155–65; G.H.R.Parkinson, ‘Spinoza on the Power<br />

and Freedom <strong>of</strong> Man’, in E.Freeman and M.Mandelbaum (eds) Spinoza: Essays in<br />

Interpretation (La Salle, Ill., Open Court, 1975), pp. 7–33. A general survey <strong>of</strong><br />

Leibniz’s views about human freedom is provided by G.H.R.Parkinson, Leibniz on<br />

Human Freedom (Wiesbaden, Steiner, 1970). See also, for example, A.Burms and<br />

H.de Dijn, ‘Freedom and Logical Contingency in Leibniz’, Studia Leibnitiana 11<br />

(1979) 124–33; Lois Frankel, ‘Being Able to do Otherwise: Leibniz on Freedom<br />

and Contingency’, Studia Leibnitiana 16 (1984) 45–59; Pauline Phemister,<br />

‘Leibniz, Free Will and Rationality’, Studia Leibnitiana 23 (1991) 25–39.<br />

40 In Descartes’s terminology, I can have a ‘clear and distinct idea’ <strong>of</strong> a mind as a<br />

being which is thinking and non-extended, but I have a clear and distinct idea <strong>of</strong> a<br />

body in so far as this is non-thinking and extended. See Meditations VI, CSM ii, p.<br />

54, and Replies to First Objections, CSM ii, p. 86.<br />

41 Gassendi’s atomism influenced the young Leibniz (see especially K.Moll, Der<br />

junge Leibniz (Stuttgart, Frommann-Holzboog, 1982), vol 2, who was also<br />

influenced by Hobbes (see, for example, J.W.N.Watkins, Hobbes’ System <strong>of</strong> Ideas<br />

(London, Hutchinson, 2nd edn, 1973), pp. 87–94). Whether Spinoza borrowed from<br />

Hobbes is a matter <strong>of</strong> controversy, but he certainly defined his position by<br />

reference to Hobbes. See, for example, A.G.Wernham, Benedict de Spinoza: The<br />

Political Works (Oxford, Clarendon, 1958), pp. 11–36.<br />

42 John Aubrey, Brief Lives and Other Selected Writings, ed. Anthony Powell<br />

(London, Cresset Press, 1949), p. 242.<br />

43 Leviathan (Oxford, Blackwell, 1946), ch. 5, p. 29.<br />

44 ibid.<br />

45 ibid., ch. 7, p. 40.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!