27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

284 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

74 E I P32C1, E I P33 and 33S1.<br />

75 E I A6, E II D4.<br />

76 cf. J.J.McIntosh, ‘Spinoza’s Epistemological Views’, in G.N.A.Vesey (ed.) Reason<br />

and Reality, Royal Institute <strong>of</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> Lectures, vol. 5 (1970–1) (London,<br />

Macmillan, 1972), p. 38; also G.H.R.Parkinson, ‘“Truth is its Own Standard”.<br />

Aspects <strong>of</strong> Spinoza’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Truth’, in Shahan and Biro [8.40], 42–5.<br />

77 In the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione (G ii, 10–12), Spinoza recognizes four<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> knowledge, the first two <strong>of</strong> which correspond to the first <strong>of</strong> the three kinds<br />

recognized in the Ethics. The Short Treatise recognizes three kinds only, but the<br />

account that it <strong>of</strong>fers <strong>of</strong> these is sketchy.<br />

78 Spinoza also counts as an example <strong>of</strong> the first kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge what he calls<br />

‘knowledge from signs’ (E II P40S2; cf. E II P18S). This raises interesting<br />

questions concerning Spinoza’s views about language, which I have discussed in my<br />

‘Language and Knowledge in Spinoza’, reprinted in Grene [8.33], 73–100.<br />

79 It is not clear how Spinoza would have attempted to justify his view that induction<br />

is a kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

80 E II P38–9, P40 and S2; cf. E V P36S.<br />

81 This is in fact a literal translation <strong>of</strong> the Greek term ‘koinai ennoai’, used by Euclid<br />

to refer to the axioms <strong>of</strong> his system.<br />

82 cf. Aristotle, Topics, I 5, 102 a18–19. On ‘essence’ in Spinoza, cf. p. 282.<br />

83 E I P33S2.<br />

84 E II P41.<br />

85 E V P31 and S.<br />

86 E V P36S.<br />

87 See also TDIE, G ii, 12, and KV II.1, G i, 54–5.<br />

88 For this conversation, see Descartes’ Conversation with Burman, ed. and trans.<br />

J.G.Cottingham (Oxford, Clarendon, 1976), esp. p. 4 (also CSM iii, 333).<br />

89 Burman’s record <strong>of</strong> the conversation remained in manuscript until 1896. In<br />

principle, Spinoza could have had access to the manuscript, but there is no<br />

evidence that he had any contact with Burman, or with the Cartesian philosopher<br />

Clauberg, who also contributed to the manuscript.<br />

90 The reference is probably to E I P15, mentioned in E V P36S. It could perhaps be<br />

to E I P25, but this itself involves a reference to E I P15.<br />

91 This doctrine, and the related doctrine <strong>of</strong> the eternity <strong>of</strong> the human mind, has been<br />

severely criticized. See, for example, Bennett [8.28], 357–63, 369–75; Delahunty<br />

[8.30], 279–305; Martha Kneale, ‘Eternity and Sempiternity’, in Grene [8.33], 227–<br />

40. A more sympathetic account is given by Joachim [8.35], 230–3, 298–309.<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY<br />

Original language editions<br />

8.1 Gebhardt, C. (ed.) Spinoza, Opera, Heidelberg, Winter, 4 vols, 1924–8.<br />

8.2 van Vloten, J. and Land, J.P.N. (eds) Benedicti de Spinoza Opera quotquot reperta<br />

sunt, The Hague, Nijh<strong>of</strong>f, 1st edn, 2 vols, 1882–3; 2nd edn, 3 vols, 1895; 3rd edn, 4<br />

vols, 1914.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!