27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

INTRODUCTION 5<br />

Born in 1561, Bacon is sometimes discussed in books on Renaissance<br />

philosophy, 16 but it is better to regard him as a modern in whom some traces <strong>of</strong><br />

the Renaissance remained. Certainly, he agreed with the Renaissance<br />

philosophers in his scorn for the scholastics; he agreed, too, with some<br />

Renaissance writers in his view that magic was not to be rejected entirely, and<br />

his views about the nature <strong>of</strong> knowledge have a Renaissance ancestry. 17 But he<br />

was as dismissive <strong>of</strong> Renaissance authors as he was <strong>of</strong> the scholastics, saying <strong>of</strong><br />

them that their concern was primarily with words. 18 He saw himself as a<br />

revolutionary, the provider <strong>of</strong> a new logic—a ‘Novum Organum’—which was to<br />

supercede the old ‘Organon’ <strong>of</strong> Aristotle. Aristotle’s logic had already been<br />

attacked by humanist logicians, <strong>of</strong> whom the most influential in the sixteenth and<br />

seventeenth centuries was Ramus (Pierre de la Ramée, 1515–72). 19 But the aims<br />

<strong>of</strong> Bacon and Ramus were quite different. Ramus was concerned with thinking in<br />

general, and his aim was to replace the Aristotelian syllogism by a less formal<br />

logic, which would correspond more closely to the way in which people actually<br />

think. 20 Bacon, on the other hand, was concerned chiefly with scientific thinking.<br />

It has been said <strong>of</strong> Bacon that he made ‘the first serious attempt to formulate<br />

and justify the procedure <strong>of</strong> natural scientists’. 21 For many, this attempt is to be<br />

found in Bacon’s discussions <strong>of</strong> induction—that is, <strong>of</strong> that type <strong>of</strong> argument in<br />

which one reaches universal conclusions from particular instances. His ‘Novum<br />

Organum’, his ‘New Instru ment’, was to be a systematic way <strong>of</strong> reaching such<br />

conclusions. Tables <strong>of</strong> observations were to be drawn up, and universal laws<br />

were to be derived from these by the application <strong>of</strong> certain rules. 22 Such laws,<br />

Bacon thought, were not wholly satisfactory, in that they told us nothing about<br />

the fundamental structure <strong>of</strong> reality; none the less, they were known, in that they<br />

provided us with rules for the manipulation <strong>of</strong> nature. 23 This introduces Bacon’s<br />

distinctive view about the nature <strong>of</strong> knowledge: namely, that to know is to make.<br />

As mentioned earlier, the view has Renaissance antecedents, but Bacon applies it<br />

to what we now regard as the beginnings <strong>of</strong> modern science. It is his emphasis on<br />

the fact that the inquirer should not just observe, but should also intervene in<br />

nature, that has led him to be called, not the first philosopher <strong>of</strong> induction, but<br />

the first philosopher <strong>of</strong> experimental science. 24<br />

Whatever its merits, Bacon’s philosophy <strong>of</strong> science also had serious<br />

deficiencies; it is widely recognized that Bacon has no grasp <strong>of</strong> the importance<br />

that mathematics has for the sciences. 25 This cannot be said <strong>of</strong> the philosophers<br />

whose ideas are the concern <strong>of</strong> over half <strong>of</strong> this volume: namely, the seventeenthcentury<br />

rationalists. As mentioned earlier, 26 the term has generated some<br />

controversy. It is used to pick out a number <strong>of</strong> seventeenth-century philosophers,<br />

the chief <strong>of</strong> whom were Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, though Malebranche<br />

and the Flemish philosopher Geulincx are also included. Now, it must be<br />

admitted that none <strong>of</strong> these ever called himself a rationalist, nor can they be said<br />

to have constituted a school, in the sense <strong>of</strong> a group <strong>of</strong> people who saw<br />

themselves as separated from others by virtue <strong>of</strong> their adherence to certain shared<br />

principles. They seem, indeed, to have been more conscious <strong>of</strong> their disagreements

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!