27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

122 SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS UP TO DESCARTES<br />

elaborately, but still vaguely, in terms <strong>of</strong> what we may call differential pressures<br />

from the vortices.<br />

Compared with Newton on this and other issues, Descartes appears a<br />

qualitative rather than a quantitative scientist, and this ties in with another<br />

important methodological difference. Newton, at least rhetorically within the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> justification, was a strong inductivist.<br />

In experimental philosophy we are to look upon propositions inferred by<br />

general induction from phenomena as accurately or very nearly true,<br />

notwithstanding any contrary hypotheses that may be imagined, till such<br />

time as other phenomena occur, by which they may either be made more<br />

accurate, or liable to exceptions. 47<br />

For Descartes and his followers, however, hypotheses played a crucial role. The<br />

general structure <strong>of</strong> matter and the general laws <strong>of</strong> motion could be reached<br />

purely by deduction, but this process could not proceed unaided to unique<br />

explanations <strong>of</strong> particular phenomena.<br />

When I wished to descend to [effects] that were more particular, so many<br />

different ones were presented to me that I did not think it possible for the<br />

human mind to distinguish the forms or species <strong>of</strong> bodies that were on<br />

Earth from an infinity <strong>of</strong> others which could have been there if it had been<br />

the will <strong>of</strong> God to put them there, nor consequently to relate them to our<br />

use without coming to the causes by means <strong>of</strong> the effects and employing<br />

several particular experiences. Following this, in passing my mind again<br />

over all the objects which were ever presented to my sense, I indeed dare to<br />

say that I have not remarked there anything that I could not explain<br />

suitably enough by the principles that I have found. But I must also admit<br />

that Nature’s power is so ample and so vast and that my principles are so<br />

simple and so general that I hardly remark any particular effect without<br />

immediately recognising that it can be deduced in many different fashions,<br />

and that my greatest difficulty is usually in finding upon which <strong>of</strong> these<br />

fashions it does depend. And for this I know no other expedient than to<br />

seek once again some experiences which are such that their outcome will<br />

not be the same if it is in one <strong>of</strong> the fashions that one must explain it as it will<br />

be if it is in the other. 48<br />

In this way Descartes gives a reasonably clear, if not unproblematic, expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> what is <strong>of</strong>ten referred to as a hypothetico-deductive methodology, <strong>of</strong> a kind<br />

which was employed by many notable scientists <strong>of</strong> the later seventeenth century.<br />

Descartes was not alone in producing a mechanical philosophy— one need<br />

only think <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Pierre Gassendi and <strong>of</strong> Thomas Hobbes—but it was his<br />

system together with later developments and modifications that was most<br />

generally influential. And when Aristotelian natural philosophy began at last to

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!