27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

278 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

knowledge, what he says about such knowledge can be illuminated by comparing<br />

it with what Descartes says about his famous utterance, Cogito, ergo sum. It is<br />

well known that Descartes denied that, in saying ‘I am thinking, therefore I<br />

exist’, he was deriving existence from thought by a kind <strong>of</strong> syllogism.<br />

(‘Everything that thinks, exists; I am a being that thinks; therefore…etc.’) (Reply<br />

to Second Objections, CSM ii, 100). Rather, he said that he recognized his<br />

existence ‘as something self-evident by a simple intuition <strong>of</strong> the mind’ (ibid.).<br />

This may seem to involve him in a difficulty which is similar to Spinoza’s:<br />

namely, that Descartes expresses this ‘simple intuition’ in what appears to be the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> an inference, in that it involves the term ‘therefore’. What is <strong>of</strong> great<br />

interest here is the solution that Descartes <strong>of</strong>fered in his conversation <strong>of</strong> 1648<br />

with the young Dutch scholar Frans Burman. 88 Burman had asked about the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> Cogito, ergo sum; in his reply, Descartes said that the universal<br />

proposition ‘Everything that thinks, exists’ is logically prior to ‘I am thinking,<br />

therefore I exist’, but that I do not need to know the former proposition before I<br />

can recognize the truth <strong>of</strong> the latter. He went on to say, ‘We do not separate out<br />

these general propositions from the particular instances; rather, it is in the<br />

particular instances that we think them’. Now, it is not suggested here that<br />

Spinoza knew <strong>of</strong> Descartes’s conversation with Burman, 89 or indeed that he<br />

would have regarded Cogito, ergo sum as an instance <strong>of</strong> the third kind <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge. The point is simply that we can make sense <strong>of</strong> what he says about<br />

intuitive knowledge by supposing him to be thinking along lines similar to those<br />

followed by Descartes. That is, when Spinoza says that, in order to discover a<br />

fourth proportional, we do not have to appeal to a universal rule but can make<br />

use <strong>of</strong> intuitive knowledge, what he means can be put in Descartes’s terms by<br />

saying that we think <strong>of</strong> the general rule in the particular instance.<br />

The question now arises whether the Ethics contains any substantive examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> the third kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge, or whether it, at best, only points the way<br />

towards such knowledge. There is <strong>of</strong> course the case <strong>of</strong> the discovery <strong>of</strong> a fourth<br />

proportional; but this is merely illustrative, and does not play an essential part in<br />

the structure <strong>of</strong> the work. However, there does seem to be an important use <strong>of</strong><br />

intuitive knowledge in the Ethics. This is to be found in Proposition 36 <strong>of</strong> Part V,<br />

together with its Corollary and Scholium. In the Scholium, Spinoza remarks that,<br />

from what he has said elsewhere in the work, ‘It is quite clear to us how and in what<br />

way our mind follows with regard to essence and existence from the divine<br />

nature and continually depends on God’, and he continues by saying that this is<br />

an example <strong>of</strong> the third kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge. The Scholium does more than give<br />

an example <strong>of</strong> the third kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge; it also shows precisely how this kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge differs from the second, and why Spinoza ascribes such<br />

importance to it. Spinoza says (ibid.) that, in the first part <strong>of</strong> the Ethics, he has<br />

already shown 90 that ‘all things (and consequently the human mind) depend on<br />

God with regard to essence and existence’. This, he says, is an example <strong>of</strong> the<br />

second kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge; what is more, the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this proposition is<br />

‘perfectly legitimate and placed beyond the reach <strong>of</strong> doubt’. We have, then, no

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!