13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

diagram-based geometric practice 71specialists suggest this is the basic tool <strong>of</strong> ancient practice, with reductio argumentfor the exclusion <strong>of</strong> putative alternatives as backup. Harari (2003) discussesthe 20th-century alternative view that constructions serve as existence pro<strong>of</strong>s.Some treatments (Miller (2001); Manders (2007), arguably) take eachdifferent-appearance diagram after an additional entry to require separatecase treatment. Using Euclid I.2 as example, Mumma (2006) shows that limitingcase branching to when a different-appearance feature is actually attributed,while sufficient for generality, vastly reduces the number <strong>of</strong> separate cases toabout what we find in Euclid and Proclus.5. Sensitivity <strong>of</strong> co-exact conditions.As long as the ‘circles’ in I.1 are continuous closed curves, no amount<strong>of</strong> distortion can eliminate intersection points. Most co-exact conditions,however, will be affected by sufficiently large distortions violating exactconditions: a ‘straight’ line segment, say, that loops out far enough, willspuriously intersect any other line in the diagram. Normal drawing practicesobviously avoid such egregious spurious co-exact conditions; nonetheless,this raises a challenge to the justificatory ability <strong>of</strong> diagram-based attribution:might we not encounter ‘sensitive’ diagram situations, where normal drawingpractices would not suffice to avoid a spurious co-exact occurrence, which ademonstration would then be entitled to attribute?Traditional practice aims to avoid such sensitive situations. There seem tobe two mechanisms.(a) By breaking up a development into a sequence <strong>of</strong> separate propositions,Euclid keeps each diagram simple: omitting construction lines from priorlemmas avoids point- and region-forming interactions with those absent lines.(b) No matter how simple a diagram, if it is too small we cannot drawit accurately enough to rely on its looks. Even a good-sized diagram mighthave too much going on in too tight a corner—in a seminar paper, MatthewWeiner trenchantly called this a ‘smudge’. I propose that a diagram in ademonstration is required to provide a clear case for its co-exact attributions,on pain <strong>of</strong> rejection. For example, to show what happens when an exactcondition fails (say in I.6, in a reductio pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the exact condition), one mustuseadiagraminwhichitfailsinanexaggeratedway.Inactualgeometricalreasoning, providing demonstrative grounds for a given co-exact attributionmight require re-drawing the diagram. We will, however, need to consider theconsequences <strong>of</strong> this proposal for the epistemology <strong>of</strong> generality in geometricaldemonstration.In the face <strong>of</strong> such complications, keep in mind that ancient diagram-basedreasoning did work! The complications are only in our understanding <strong>of</strong> whyit works.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!