13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

visualizing in mathematics 23Pasch said, and he was echoed by Hilbert and Russell (Pasch, 1882; Hilbert,1894; Russell, 1901).In some quarters this turn led to a general disdain for visual thinking inmathematics: ‘In the best books’ Russell pronounced ‘there are no figures atall.’ (Russell, 1901). Although this attitude was opposed by some prominentmathematicians, others took it to heart. Landau, for example, wrote a calculustextbook without a single diagram (Landau, 1934). But the predominant viewwasnotsoextreme:thinkinginterms<strong>of</strong>figureswasvaluedasameans<strong>of</strong>facilitating grasp <strong>of</strong> formulae and linguistic text, but only reasoning expressedby means <strong>of</strong> formulae and text could bear any epistemological weight.By the late 20th century the mood had swung back in favour <strong>of</strong> visualization:<strong>Mancosu</strong> (2005) provides an excellent survey. We find books that advertisetheir defiance <strong>of</strong> anti-visual puritanism in their titles, such as Visual Geometryand Topology (Fomenko, 1994) andVisual Complex Analysis (Needham, 1997);mathematics educators turn their attention to pedagogical uses <strong>of</strong> visualization(Zimmermann and Cunningham, 1991); the use <strong>of</strong> computer-generatedimagery begins to bear fruit at research level (H<strong>of</strong>fman, 1987; Palais, 1999);and diagrams find their way into research papers in abstract fields: see forexample the papers on higher dimensional category theory by Joyal et al.(1996), Leinster (2004), and Lauda (2005). But attitudes to the epistemology<strong>of</strong> visual thinking remain mixed. The discussion is almost entirely confined tothe role <strong>of</strong> diagrams in pro<strong>of</strong>s. In some cases, it is claimed, a picture alone isa pro<strong>of</strong> (Brown, 1999, Ch.3). But that view is rare. Even the editor <strong>of</strong> Pro<strong>of</strong>swithout Words: Exercises in Visual Thinking, writes ‘Of course, ‘‘pro<strong>of</strong>s withoutwords’’ are not really pro<strong>of</strong>s’ (Nelsen, 1993, p. vi). At the other extreme is thestolid attitude <strong>of</strong> Tennant (1986, p.304):[the diagram] has no proper place in the pro<strong>of</strong> as such. For the pro<strong>of</strong> is a syntacticobject consisting only <strong>of</strong> sentences arranged in a finite and inspectable array.Between the extremes, others hold that, even if no picture alone is a pro<strong>of</strong>,visual images can have a non-superfluous role in reasoning that constitutes apro<strong>of</strong> (Barwise and Etchemendy, 1996a; Norman, 2006). Visual representations,such as geometric diagrams, graphs, and maps, all carry information. Takingvalid deductive reasoning to be the reliable extraction <strong>of</strong> information frominformation already obtained, Barwise and Etchemendy (1996a) pose thefollowing question: Why cannot the representations composing a pro<strong>of</strong> bevisual as well as linguistic? The sole reason for denying this role to visualrepresentations is the thought that, with the possible exception <strong>of</strong> veryrestricted cases, visual thinking is unreliable, hence cannot contribute to pro<strong>of</strong>.In the next section I probe this matter by considering visualization in proving,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!