13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

purity as an ideal <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> 187even the reliability <strong>of</strong> geometrical thinking as regards continuity phenomena.¹⁵Analysts <strong>of</strong> the latter half <strong>of</strong> the 19th century thus had, if anything, evenstronger reasons to try to rid analysis <strong>of</strong> geometrical thinking.An important example is Dedekind, who expressed his commitment topurity this way:In discussing the notion <strong>of</strong> the approach <strong>of</strong> a variable magnitude to a fixed limitingvalue ... I had recourse to geometric evidences. Even now such resort to geometricintuition ... I regard as exceedingly useful, from the didactic standpoint ... . Butthat this form <strong>of</strong> introduction into the differential calculus can make no claim tobeing scientific, no one will deny. For myself this feeling <strong>of</strong> dissatisfaction was sooverpowering that I made the fixed resolve to ... find a purely arithmetical andperfectly rigorous foundation for the principles <strong>of</strong> infinitesimal analysis.Dedekind (1872, 1–2)Elsewhere Dedekind stated as the first procedural demand on his theory <strong>of</strong>algebraic integers that ‘arithmetic remain free from intermingling with foreignelements (mélange d’éléments étrangers)’ (Dedekind, 1877, 269). This meant forhim that ‘the definition ... <strong>of</strong> irrational number ought to be based on phenomenaone can already define clearly in the domain R <strong>of</strong> rational numbers’ (loc. cit.).Dedekind’s fellow logicist, Frege, also accepted purity as an ideal. Indeed,he described it as a principal motive for his logicist program, one which set itapart from the misbegotten attempt by Gauss to found complex arithmetic ongeometry.¹⁶The overcoming <strong>of</strong> this reluctance [to accept complex numbers, MD] wasfacilitated by geometrical interpretations; but with these, something foreign wasintroduced into arithmetic. Inevitably there arose the desire <strong>of</strong> ... extruding thesegeometrical aspects. It appeared contrary to all reason that purely arithmeticaltheorems should rest on geometrical axioms; and it was inevitable that pro<strong>of</strong>swhich apparently established such a dependence should seem to obscure the truestate <strong>of</strong> affairs. The task <strong>of</strong> deriving what was arithmetical by purely arithmeticalmeans, i.e. purely logically, could not be put <strong>of</strong>f.Frege (1885, 116–117)¹⁷¹⁵ Bolzano himself discovered a function <strong>of</strong> this type in 1834. The work in which this was done(namely, Bolzano, 1834, §75), however, was not published until 1930.¹⁶ As noted above, Gauss himself conceded the impurity <strong>of</strong> his geometrical interpretation in hislater writings. In his 1831 essay, however, he credited it with providing a sensible representation <strong>of</strong>the complexes ‘that leaves nothing to be desired’ (Gauss, 1832, 311). ‘[O]ne needs’, he said, ‘nothingfurther to bring this quantity [i.e. √ −1, MD] into the domain <strong>of</strong> the objects <strong>of</strong> arithmetic’ (Gauss,1832, 313). It should perhaps also be noted here that, towards the end <strong>of</strong> his life, Frege returned to theidea <strong>of</strong> a geometrical foundation for arithmetic.¹⁷ See Frege (1884, §§103–104) for similar statements.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!