13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

224 michael hallettfor the first time we subject the means <strong>of</strong> carrying out a pro<strong>of</strong> to a critical analysis.(Hilbert ( ∗ 1898/1899, p.30), p. 236 in Hallett and Majer (2004))Then follow the general remarks about ‘purity <strong>of</strong> method’ which were quotedearlier (see p. 282). What this passage raises is the question <strong>of</strong> the appropriateness<strong>of</strong> a given pro<strong>of</strong>, a ‘purity’ question par excellence, for here we have to do witha theorem, the Planar Desargues’s Theorem, which is proved by means whichat first sight might be thought inappropriate, owing to the pro<strong>of</strong>’s appeal tospatial axioms.What we are faced with first is an independence question, and Hilbert setsout to show that the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Planar Desargues’s Theorem is not possiblewithout appeal to spatial incidence axioms. As he puts it:We will rather show that Desargues’s Theorem is unprovable by means <strong>of</strong> I 1–2,II 1–5. One will thus be spared the trouble <strong>of</strong> looking for a pro<strong>of</strong> in the plane.For us, this is the first, simplest example for the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> unprovability. Indeed:Tosatisfy us, it is necessary either to find a pro<strong>of</strong> which operates just in the plane, or toshow that there is no such pro<strong>of</strong>. Prove so, that we specify a system <strong>of</strong> things = pointsand things = planes for which axioms I 1–2, II1–5 hold, but the DesarguesTheorem does not, i.e., that a plane geometry with the axioms I, II is possiblewithout the Desargues Theorem. (Hilbert ( ∗ 1898/1899, p.30), pp. 236–237 inHallett and Majer (2004))To show this, Hilbert constructs an analytic plane <strong>of</strong> real numbers, with theclosed interval [0, +∞] removed. The key thing is that some <strong>of</strong> the newstraight lines are gerrymandered compositions: below the x-axis, the line is anordinary straight (half-)line; above the x-axis, the line is in fact an arc <strong>of</strong> a circleuniquely determined by the conditions (a) that it goes ‘through’ the origin,O (it is open-ended here, since O is not itself in the model), and (b) that thegiven straight line below the x-axis is a tangent to it. Hilbert’s figure (Fig. 8.2)illustrates the essentials <strong>of</strong> the model.²⁷The first thing to note about this is that we are here operating at one removefrom the intuition ordinarily thought to underlie projective geometry. For onething, the model produces highly unintuitive ‘straight lines’, even though theyare pieced together using intuitable objects. The gerrymandered ‘straight lines’are again ‘intuitable’ in the sense that one can easily visualize them (witnessFig. 8.2). Moreover, there is a sense in which lines made up <strong>of</strong> two distinctpieces are extremely familiar to us; think <strong>of</strong> a straight stick (a line segment) halfimmersed in still, clear water and then viewed from above looking down intothe water. (Indeed, if it is viewed when the water is not still, then at any instant²⁷ For full details, see Hilbert ( ∗ 1898/1899, 31), or the Ausarbeitung, p.28; these are pp. 237 and 316respectively in Hallett and Majer (2004).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!