13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4The Euclidean Diagram (1995)KENNETH MANDERS[Geometrical] figures must also be regarded as characters, for the circle describedon paper is not a true circle and need not be; it is enough that we take it for acircle.(Loemker, Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, p. 84.)In Euclidean geometry, a diagram has standing to license inference, just as dorelationships recognized in the text. It is now commonly held that this is a defect<strong>of</strong> rigor. But the extraordinary career <strong>of</strong> Euclidean practice justifies a fullerconsideration. It was a stable and fruitful tool <strong>of</strong> investigation across diversecultural contexts for over two thousand years. During that time, it generallystruck thoughtful and knowledgeable people as the most rigorous <strong>of</strong> humanways <strong>of</strong> knowing, even in the face <strong>of</strong> centuries <strong>of</strong> internal criticism in antiquity.We here undertake to reconstruct the role <strong>of</strong> diagrams in the inferentialstandards <strong>of</strong> Euclidean practice, seeking a more accurate view <strong>of</strong> the strengthsand weaknesses <strong>of</strong> traditional geometrical argument. It is interesting to reclaimour philosophical grip on traditional geometrical reasoning especially becausesuch reasoning coordinates two means <strong>of</strong> expression with very differentcharacteristics: diagrams and ordinary text-based argument. Philosophers <strong>of</strong> ourage seem to have ignored such representational contrasts, which nonethelessappear to be <strong>of</strong> great interest.If it is to give a non-trivial grip on life, in its particular way, an intellectualpractice must give us—all too finite and human beings—a game we can play;and play well, together, and to our pr<strong>of</strong>it. To succeed in this, intellectualpractices harness our abilities to engage their artifacts, as I will call it: toproduce, preserve, and respond to artifacts in controlled ways—to play games,Research supported by NSF Grants DIR-90-23955 and SBER-94-12895, and a Howard FoundationFellowship for 1994/95.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!