13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

mathematics and physics: strategies <strong>of</strong> assimilation 427and every step in the calculation can be given a clear semantical interpretationin the world <strong>of</strong> set-theoretical and category-theoretic constructions.It would be a mistake, though, to see Rota’s interpretation as simply bestowinglegitimacy on a previously dubious mathematical technique. The interpretationbears fruit in other directions. The embedding <strong>of</strong> combinatorially definedsequences in the algebra <strong>of</strong> formal power series is heuristically very fertile, andenables a systematic treatment <strong>of</strong> special functions. Furthermore, the interpretationmakes contact with a large tract <strong>of</strong> more recent mathematics, such as categorytheory with its fruitful notion <strong>of</strong> adjoints. The marriage <strong>of</strong> 19th-centuryformal calculation with modern abstract theory produces a sturdy <strong>of</strong>fspring.Let us look back over this example to see if we can extract some interestinggeneral features. In the case <strong>of</strong> the umbral calculus, as in many <strong>of</strong> the other caseswe discuss, computations are primary. However, the lack <strong>of</strong> a clear semanticsfor the objects manipulated leads mathematicians to treat the methods withdistrust, no matter how successful the computations.Rota’s reinterpretation <strong>of</strong> the umbral calculus has two features that we candetect elsewhere in the work <strong>of</strong> assimilation. First, the logic is reinterpreted.The umbral calculationis rewritten as(B + 1) 2 = B 2 + 2B 1 + 1 = B 2 + 2B 1 + 1L((U +1) 2 ) = L(U 2 + 2U + 1) = L(U 2 ) + 2L(U) + L(1) = B 2 + 2B 1 + 1.The introduction <strong>of</strong> the linear operator L allows the dubious move <strong>of</strong> raisingand lowering indices to be explained simply as a transition between twoisomorphic domains <strong>of</strong> calculation. Second, the reinterpretation involves theintroduction <strong>of</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> higher type, in this case linear functionals acting onthe space <strong>of</strong> polynomials in one variable.This reinterpretation <strong>of</strong> logic and the introduction <strong>of</strong> higher type entities toprovide a semantics is also visible in the theory <strong>of</strong> infinitesimals. Robinson’snonstandard universe is composed <strong>of</strong> equivalence classes <strong>of</strong> higher type objects,since the hyperreals are elements <strong>of</strong> an ultrapower <strong>of</strong> a standard model (Goldblatt,1988). Equations that involve treating infinitesimals as zero quantities(the kind <strong>of</strong> thing to which Berkeley raised objections), such as 2 + ɛ = 2, arereinterpreted in Robinson’s framework as 2 + ɛ ≈ 2, where x ≈ y means thatx and y are infinitely close (and hence have the same standard part). Interestingly,in the framework <strong>of</strong> smooth analysis, equations such as 2 + ɛ 2 = 2canbe literally true, where ɛ is a nilpotent infinitesimal; the price we have to payfor this literal interpretation <strong>of</strong> equations is the abandonment <strong>of</strong> classical logic.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!