13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

the euclidean diagram (1995) 91diagram, rather than inferred from prior entries in the text, require not justequality but instead its most explicit possible form: coincidence that arises inan extremely direct way from the constraints under which the (imperfect)diagram is produced; such as the common side in the triangles which arisein the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> I.6. This restriction on diagram-based attribution is not sosurprising, as equality among less directly related diagram elements cannotbe controlled by the standards under which diagrams are produced; but therestriction applies just so to inequality (which appears to pass our ‘co-exactness’stability test below).A striking example is Euclid I.20, ‘any two sides <strong>of</strong> the triangle takentogether are greater than the third.’ The sometimes maligned requirementthat this diagrammatically evident fact be proved no doubt reflects a relativelyadvanced theoretical foundational development in Greek geometry; but it isthat tradition so developed which we are to characterize. Geometrical reasoningfrequently obtains inequalities directly from the diagram, but (corresponding tothe restriction for equality) only when an object in the diagram is a proper part<strong>of</strong> another, rather than from any kind <strong>of</strong> indirect comparison. Equalities andinequalities (greater, less) among objects distributed throughout the diagramare <strong>of</strong> great importance, and inference principles for both are available withinthe discursive text. In order to allow these notions to function also in diagrambasedgeometrical argument, the Elements makes it its first order <strong>of</strong> businessto secure their transfer around the diagram so that direct comparisons may bemade (notably, I.2, I.3, I.4): both (i) so that inequalities already available inthe discursive text may be realized as proper inclusions in the diagram (I.6),and (ii) so that inequalities in the diagram may be related to explicit inclusionsthere which then may be read <strong>of</strong>f (I.16).4.2.2 Exact and co-exact attributionGeometric attribution standards may be understood further by distinguishingwhat will be called exact and co-exact attributes. Typical alleged ‘fallacies <strong>of</strong>diagram use’ rest on taking it for granted that an—to the eye apparentlyrealized but false—exact condition would be read <strong>of</strong>f from a diagram; butthe practice never allows an exact condition to be read <strong>of</strong>f from the diagram.Typical ‘gaps in Euclid’ involve reading <strong>of</strong>f some explicit co-exact feature froma diagram; and this is permissable. It will not be hard to discover a rationalefor this: the distinction <strong>of</strong> exact/co-exact attributes is directly related to whatresources the practice has to control the production <strong>of</strong> diagrams and provide forresolution <strong>of</strong> disagreement among judgements based on their appearances. Thepractice has resources to limit the risk <strong>of</strong> disagreement on (explicit) co-exactattributions from a diagram; but it lacks such resources for exact attributions,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!