13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

330 jeremy avigadto screen <strong>of</strong>f extraneous beliefs and desires, and assume nothing about anagent’s intent beyond the intent to perform mathematically. I am certainly notclaiming that it is obvious that one can provide adequate characterizations <strong>of</strong>the circumstances under which we tend to ascribe mathematical understanding;only that it is not obvious that attempts to do so are doomed to failure.Perhaps the most compelling criticism <strong>of</strong> a dispositional account is that evenif we could characterize the behaviors that are correlated with the mentalstates under consideration, identifying the mental states with the associatedbehaviors simply tells the wrong kind <strong>of</strong> story. We expect a philosophicaltheory to provide some sort <strong>of</strong> causal explanation that tells us how intelligentand intentional behavior is brought about; it seems unsatisfying to identify‘knowing how to play the piano’ with successful performance, when whatone really wants <strong>of</strong> a theory is an account <strong>of</strong> the mental activity that makessuch performance possible. In the case at hand, we would like a theory thatexplains how a proper understanding enables one to function mathematically.This insistence has not only an intuitive appeal, but also a pragmatic one. Forexample, in so far as our theory is to be relevant to mathematical expositionand pedagogy, we would expect it not only to characterize the outward signs<strong>of</strong> mathematical understanding, but also provide some hints as to how they canbe encouraged and taught. Similarly, I take it that a theory <strong>of</strong> mathematicalunderstanding should be <strong>of</strong> service to computer scientists trying to writes<strong>of</strong>tware that exhibits various types <strong>of</strong> competent mathematical behavior.Even if we set aside the question as to whether it is appropriate to attribute‘understanding’ to a computer, we might expect a good philosophical theorynot just to clarify and characterize the desired behaviors, but also to providesome guidance in bringing them about.We are therefore tempted to renounce our therapy and try, again, to figureout just what understanding really is. What saves us, however, is the observationthat our theory <strong>of</strong> mathematical abilities need not degenerate to a laundry list<strong>of</strong> behavioral cues. The abilities we describe will interact in complex ways,and will not always be cast in terms <strong>of</strong> behavioral manifestations. Consider ourexplanation <strong>of</strong> what it means for Paolo to understand group theory. Some <strong>of</strong>the relevant abilities may be cast in terms <strong>of</strong> behaviors, for example, the abilityto state a theorem or answer a question appropriately. But others may be castin more abstract terms, such as the ability to ‘recognize’ a group structure,‘determine’ subgroups and cosets, ‘apply’ a lemma, or ‘recall’ a fundamentalfact. In fact, we <strong>of</strong>ten take these abstract abilities to provide the ‘mechanisms’that explain the observable behaviors. We may be relieved to learn that ourWittgensteinian training does not preclude talk <strong>of</strong> mechanisms, provided thatwe keep in mind that ‘these mechanisms are only hypotheses, models designed

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!