13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

visualizing in mathematics 29thinking, a topic I will have to leave aside. In the following discussion I willassume that appropriate text is present.The conclusion drawn is that the sum <strong>of</strong> integers from 1 to n is [n×(n + 1)]/2 for any positive integer n, but the diagram presents the case only forn = 6. We can perhaps avoid representing a particular number <strong>of</strong> dots whenwe merely imagine a display <strong>of</strong> the relevant kind; or if a particular number isrepresented, our experience may not make us aware <strong>of</strong> the number—just as,when one imagines the sky on a starry night, for no particular number k arewe aware that exactly k stars are represented. Even so, there is likely to besome extra specificity. For example, in imagining an array <strong>of</strong> dots <strong>of</strong> the formjust illustrated, one is unlikely to imagine just two columns <strong>of</strong> three dots, therectangular array for n = 2. Typically the subject will be aware <strong>of</strong> imaginingan array with more than two columns. This entails that an image is likely tohave unintended exclusions. In this case it would exclude the three-by-twoarray. An image <strong>of</strong> a triangle representing all angles as acute would excludetriangles with an obtuse angle or a right angle. The danger is that the visualreasoning will not be valid for the cases that are unintentionally excluded bythe visual representation, with the result that the step to the conclusion is anunwarranted generalization.What should we make <strong>of</strong> this? First, let us note that in a few cases the imageor diagram will not be over-specific. When in geometry all instances <strong>of</strong> therelevant class are similar to one another, for instance all circles or all squares,the image or diagram will not be over-specific for a generalization about thatclass; so there will be no unintended exclusions and no danger <strong>of</strong> unwarrantedgeneralization. Here then are possibilities for non-superfluous visual thinkingin proving.To get clear about the other cases, where there is a danger <strong>of</strong> overgeneralization,it helps to look at generalization in ordinary non-visual reasoning.Schematically put, in reasoning about things <strong>of</strong> kind K, once we have shownthat from certain premisses it follows that such-and-such a condition is true <strong>of</strong>arbitrary instance c, we can validly infer from those same premisses that thatcondition is true <strong>of</strong> all Ks, with the proviso that neither the condition norany premiss mentions c. (If a premiss or the condition does mention c, thereasoning may depend on a property <strong>of</strong> c that is not shared by all other Ks,and so the generalization would be unsafe.) A question we face is whether infollowing an argument involving generalization on an arbitrary instance,⁴ thethinking must include a conscious, explicit check that the proviso⁵ is met. It is⁴ Other terms for this are ‘universal generalization’ and ‘universal quantifier introduction’.⁵ The proviso is that neither the condition nor any premiss mentions c.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!