13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

30 marcus giaquintoclearly not enough that the proviso is in fact met. For in that case it might justbe the thinker’s good luck that the proviso is met; hence the thinker would notknow that the generalization is valid and so would not have genuinely thoughtthrough the pro<strong>of</strong> at that step. This leaves two options. The strict option isthat without a conscious, explicit check one has not really thought throughthe pro<strong>of</strong>. The relaxed option is that one can properly think through the pro<strong>of</strong>without checking that the proviso is met, but only if one is sensitive to thepotential error and would detect it in otherwise similar arguments. For thenone is not just lucky that the proviso is met. Being sensitive in this contextconsists in being alert to dependence on features <strong>of</strong> the arbitrary instance notshared by all members <strong>of</strong> the class <strong>of</strong> generalization, a state produced by acombination <strong>of</strong> past experience and current vigilance. Without a compellingreason to prefer one <strong>of</strong> these options, decisions on what is to count as provingmust be conditional.How does all this apply to generalizing from visual thinking about anarbitrary instance? Take the example <strong>of</strong> the visual route to the formula fortriangular numbers just indicated. The image used reveals that the formulaholds for the 6th triangular number. The generalization to all triangularnumbers is justified only if the visuo-spatial method used is applicable to thenth triangular number for all positive integers n, that is, provided that themethod used does not depend on a property not shared by all positive integers.A conscious, explicit check that this proviso is met requires making explicitthe method exemplified for 6 and proving that the method is applicablefor all positive integers in place <strong>of</strong> 6. For a similar idea in the context <strong>of</strong>automating visual arguments, see Jamnik (2001). This is not done in practicewhen thinking visually, so if we accept the strict option for thinking through apro<strong>of</strong> involving generalization, we would have to accept that the visual routeto the formula for triangular numbers does not amount to thinking througha pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> it; and the same would apply to the familiar visual routes to othergeneral positive integer formulas, such as that n 2 = the sum <strong>of</strong> the first n oddnumbers.But what if the strict option for proving by generalization on an arbitraryinstance is too strict, and the relaxed option is right? When arriving at theformula in the visual way indicated, one does not pay attention to the fact thatthe visual display represents the situation for the 6th triangular number; it is asif the mind had somehow extracted a general schema <strong>of</strong> visual reasoning fromexposure to the particular case, and had then proceeded to reason schematically,converting a schematic result into a universal proposition. What is required,on the relaxed option, is sensitivity to the possibility that the schema is notapplicable to all positive integers; one must be so alert to ways a schema <strong>of</strong> the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!