13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

understanding pro<strong>of</strong>s 319theorem is true by exhibiting a pro<strong>of</strong>; thus, it has been a primary task <strong>of</strong> thephilosophy <strong>of</strong> mathematics to clarify the notion <strong>of</strong> a mathematical pro<strong>of</strong>, andto explain how such pro<strong>of</strong>s are capable <strong>of</strong> providing appropriate mathematicalknowledge. <strong>Mathematical</strong> logic and the theory <strong>of</strong> formal axiomatic systemshave done a remarkably good job <strong>of</strong> addressing the first task, providing idealizedaccounts <strong>of</strong> the standards by which a pro<strong>of</strong> is judged to be correct. This, in and<strong>of</strong> itself, does not address more difficult questions as to what ultimately justifiesa particular choice <strong>of</strong> axiomatic framework. But, as far as it goes, the moderntheory <strong>of</strong> deductive pro<strong>of</strong> accords well with both intuition and mathematicalpractice, and has had practical applications in both mathematics and computerscience, to boot.But in mathematics one finds many types <strong>of</strong> judgment that extend beyondevaluations <strong>of</strong> correctness. For example, we seem to feel that there is adifference between knowing that a mathematical claim is true, and understandingwhy such a claim is true. Similarly, we may be able to convince ourselves thata pro<strong>of</strong> is correct by checking each inference carefully, and yet still feel asthough we do not fully understand it. The words ‘definition’ and ‘concept’seem to have different connotations: someone may know the definition <strong>of</strong>a group, without having fully understood the group concept. The fact thatthere is a gap between knowledge and understanding is made pointedly clearby the fact that one <strong>of</strong>ten finds dozens <strong>of</strong> published pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> a theoremin the literature, all <strong>of</strong> which are deemed important contributions, evenafter the first one has been accepted as correct. Later pro<strong>of</strong>s do not addto our knowledge that the resulting theorem is correct, but they somehowaugment our understanding. Our task is to make sense <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong>contribution.The observation that modern logic fails to account for important classes <strong>of</strong>judgments traces back to the early days <strong>of</strong> modern logic itself. Poincaré wrotein Science et Méthode (1908):Does understanding the demonstration <strong>of</strong> a theorem consist in examining each<strong>of</strong> the syllogisms <strong>of</strong> which it is composed in succession, and being convincedthat it is correct and conforms to the rules <strong>of</strong> the game? In the same way, doesunderstanding a definition consist simply in recognizing that the meaning <strong>of</strong> allthe terms employed is already known, and being convinced that it involves nocontradiction?... Almost all are more exacting; they want to know not only whether all thesyllogisms <strong>of</strong> a demonstration are correct, but why they are linked together inone order rather than in another. As long as they appear to them engendered bycaprice, and not by an intelligence constantly conscious <strong>of</strong> the end to be attained,they do not think they have understood. (Book II, Chapter II, p. 118)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!