13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mathematical concepts and definitions 259arise in mathematical practice as somehow ‘merely pragmatic’ questions <strong>of</strong>‘mathematical convenience’?⁴ Here too we can’t evaluate the importance <strong>of</strong>mathematical practice for the metaphysical questions unless we get a bettersense <strong>of</strong> just what theoretical choices are involved. To make progress we needillustrations with enough meat on them to make clear how rich and intricatejudgements <strong>of</strong> naturalness can be in practice. The next two sections sketch twoexamples.9.3 Fruitfulness and stipulative definition:the Legendre symbolSpivak’s remark suggests that one <strong>of</strong> the criteria identifying ‘properly defined’terms is that they are fruitful, in that they support ‘trivial’ results with ‘significantconsequences’. It is an important part <strong>of</strong> the picture that the consequencesare ‘significant’. (Any theorem will have infinitely many consequences, fromtrivial inferences like A ⊢ A&A.) So what makes a consequence ‘significant’?I won’t consider everything here, but one will be especially relevant in thesequel: a consequence is held in practice to be significant if it contributesto addressing salient ‘why?’ questions. Evaluations <strong>of</strong> the explanatoriness <strong>of</strong>arguments (theories, principles, etc.) and evaluations <strong>of</strong> the fruitfulness <strong>of</strong>definitions (theories, principles, etc.) interact in ways that make them hard tosurgically separate. I’m not suggesting that considerations about explanationexhaust the considerations relevant to assessing whether or not a consequenceis significant or a concept fruitful because it has significant consequences. I’mjust making the mild observation that explanation is easier to nail down andbetter explored than other contributors to assessments <strong>of</strong> significance, so itis helpful as a benchmark. As a contrast, it is also common for pro<strong>of</strong>s andprinciples to be preferred because they are viewed as more natural.⁵ However,⁴ This is a pivotal argumentative support in Sider (1996) to cite just one example. Discussion <strong>of</strong> thearguments would go beyond this survey, so I’ll leave it for the companion article.⁵ For example, many number theorists count the cyclotomic pro<strong>of</strong> as particularly natural. (Frölichand Taylor, 1991, p.204) opine that this pro<strong>of</strong> is ‘most natural’ (or rather: ‘ ‘‘most natural’’ ’). Similarly,in the expository account <strong>of</strong> Artin’s life by Lenstra and Stevenhagen (2000, p.48) we read: ‘Artin’sreciprocity law over Q generalizes the quadratic reciprocity law and it may be thought that itsmysteries lie deeper. Quite the opposite is true: the added generality is the first step on the wayto a natural pro<strong>of</strong>. It depends on the study <strong>of</strong> cyclotomic extensions.’ (p. 48). Gauss, on the otherhand, though one <strong>of</strong> his pro<strong>of</strong>s exploits cyclotomy, preferred a more direct argument using whatis now called ‘Gauss’s lemma’. Of other pro<strong>of</strong>s he wrote: ‘Although these pro<strong>of</strong>s leave nothing tobe desired as regards rigor, they are derived from sources much too remote... I do not hesitate tosay that until now a natural pro<strong>of</strong> has not been produced.’ (Gauss, 1808, p.1). Gauss might have

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!