13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mathematics and physics: strategies <strong>of</strong> assimilation 429experiment or computer simulation, then they are much less inclined thanthe pure mathematicians to examine the pedigree <strong>of</strong> a successful piece <strong>of</strong>machinery for calculation. This appears most flagrantly in the case <strong>of</strong> quantumfield theory. In this case, we have a calculational device (Feynman diagrams)that produces answers that agree to nine decimal places with the measuredvalue <strong>of</strong> certain physical quantities. As a consequence, the physicists havecomplete trust in the technique, even though it appears that it still seems toelude a full mathematical formulation (Johnson and Lapidus, 2000).The situation, though, is mathematically unstable, because the physicistscan <strong>of</strong>ten compute certain quantities, and ‘prove’ them to their own satisfaction,while employing the powerful but unrigorous methods peculiarto their own fields. In the introductory chapter, I mentioned two strategiesthat mathematicians can adopt in dealing with anomalous practices<strong>of</strong> reasoning and computation. The first is to prove all <strong>of</strong> the establishedresults by conventional means. This is <strong>of</strong> course a perfectly reasonable idea,though it still leaves unanswered the question: just why do these outrageoustechniques work?The entities that appear in these calculations, such as infinitesimals orrepresentative variables, are logically anomalous objects. Anomalous objectsin my sense are a little like Imre Lakatos’ monsters, but anomalous in aneven stronger sense, namely not just falling outside a standard definition, butviolating fundamental mathematical principles.An interesting example <strong>of</strong> an anomalous object is the Dirac delta function.When it first made its appearance in the physics literature, it was explained asa function δ defined on the real line so that it was zero everywhere except atthe origin, but the integral <strong>of</strong> the function was 1:∫δ(x)dx = 1.All this is very plausible from the physical point <strong>of</strong> view. If we think <strong>of</strong> δ asrepresenting the mass density function <strong>of</strong> a point particle <strong>of</strong> mass 1 situated atthe origin, then the delta function has exactly the right properties. The troubleis, there is no such function. It’s very easy to show using standard calculus thatthere simply is no such function defined on the classical real line.We are caught in a dilemma. The physicists have postulated an object that,classically speaking, simply doesn’t exist, a logical contradiction. There arevarious attitudes that one can take to this.The first is simply to dismiss the unruly objects as nonsense, a commonattitude among mathematicians. It is not hard to cite mathematicians who tookjust such an attitude to objects like the Dirac delta function. For example,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!