13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

purity <strong>of</strong> method in hilbert’s grundlagen 201At the end <strong>of</strong> the main part <strong>of</strong> the Ausarbeitung, there is the following statementabout unprovability results:An essential part <strong>of</strong> our investigation consisted in pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the unprovability <strong>of</strong>certain propositions; in conclusion, we recall that pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> this kind play a largerole in modern mathematics, and have shown themselves to be fruitful. One onlyhas to think <strong>of</strong> the squaring <strong>of</strong> the circle, <strong>of</strong> the solution <strong>of</strong> equations <strong>of</strong> the fifthdegree by extracting roots, Poincaré’s theorem that there are no unique integralsexcept for the known ones, etc. (Hilbert ( ∗ 1899, p.169), p. 392 <strong>of</strong> Hallett andMajer (2004))⁴In his own notes for these lectures, Hilbert writes:The subjects we deal with here are old, originating with Euclid: the principle<strong>of</strong> the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> unprovability is modern and arises first with two problems, thesquaring <strong>of</strong> the circle and the Parallel Axiom. However, we wish toset this as a modern principle: One should not stand aside when something inmathematics does not succeed; one should only be satisfied when we have gainedinsight into its unprovability. Most fruitful and deepest principle in mathematics.(Hilbert ( ∗ 1898/1899, p.106), p. 284 in Hallett and Majer (2004))Moreover, earlier in his notes Hilbert had written the following (theparticular example concerned will be discussed in Section 8.4.1; for themoment the details do not matter):Thus here for the first time we subject the means <strong>of</strong> carrying out a pro<strong>of</strong> to a criticalanalysis. It is modern everywhere to guarantee the purity <strong>of</strong> method. Indeed, thisis quite in order. In many cases our understanding is not satisfied when, in a pro<strong>of</strong><strong>of</strong> a proposition <strong>of</strong> arithmetic, we appeal to geometry, or in proving a geometricaltruth we draw on function theory.⁵But Hilbert immediately goes on to say this:Nevertheless, drawing on differently constituted means has frequently a deeperand justified ground, and this has uncovered beautiful and fruitful relations; e.g.the prime number problem and the ζ(x) function, potential theory and analyticfunctions, etc. In any case, one should never leave such an occurrence <strong>of</strong> themutual interaction <strong>of</strong> different domains unattended. (Hilbert ( ∗ 1898/1899,p.30),p. 237 <strong>of</strong> Hallett and Majer (2004))Thus, even while he acknowledges the epistemological disquiet behindmany purity questions, Hilbert admits that ‘impure’ mixtures might point⁴ Bibliographical items with the date preceded by an asterisk were unpublished by Hilbert.⁵ This remark has a special interest in view <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the examples I will present later, namely thatconcerning the analysis <strong>of</strong> the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the elementary Isoceles Triangle Theorem.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!