13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

mathematical concepts: fruitfulness and naturalness 297consider the property <strong>of</strong> ramification for complex functions and generalizednumbers.¹⁹ Among the singularities Riemann recognized to be especiallyimportant are branch points (a.k.a. ramification points). With proper stage setting,these can be understood as points where the function behaves locally likez ↦→ z e ,withe > 1. When dealing with number fields, the idea <strong>of</strong> primedecomposition can be generalized so that generalized numbers (ideals) can bewritten as products <strong>of</strong> generalized primes i :n∏i=1The generalized number is said to ramify if e i > 1 for any i. This point <strong>of</strong>contact between complex analysis and algebraic number theory was alreadypointed out by Dedekind and Weber.Of course, in one sense this particular connection is laying on the surface <strong>of</strong>the algebraic representations. In both cases you have exponents—either greaterthan one or equal to one—sitting right there just waiting to be noticed. But ifall we know is that some exponent is greater than one, we have no reason to getexcited, or judge there to be a point <strong>of</strong> similarity robust enough to warrant theintroduction <strong>of</strong> new terminology. The point <strong>of</strong> similarity could be a superficialaccident <strong>of</strong> the representation, or a mathematically inert coincidence. Thebedrock support for the claim that this is a genuine point <strong>of</strong> deep similarityis the fact that powerful general theorems can be proven which exploit theanalogy. Had it turned out that, at a more advanced point <strong>of</strong> reckoning, nointeresting theorems emerged, the shared terminology would stand like theword ‘elliptic’ in the phrase ‘elliptic curve’ as a quaint reminder <strong>of</strong> a connectionthat once seemed to matter. As always, the aesthetic judgements, assessments<strong>of</strong> the depth <strong>of</strong> a similarity, judgements about appropriateness <strong>of</strong> techniques,evaluations <strong>of</strong> relative simplicity, etc. are subordinated to the fundamentalbottom-line consideration: does it lead to genuinely interesting new results?Without the sine qua non <strong>of</strong> fruitfulness, the other considerations are countedas ultimately incidental.Riemann’s envisioned connection between correct definition and fruitfulnesswas revolutionary at the time, but now seems familiar, even banal. Indeed,it is fair to say that it is the dominant attitude among contemporary mathematicians.It is hardly pr<strong>of</strong>ound or surprizing that mathematicians typically e iiwhat is needed for the analogy to be complete, etc. (Weil also spells out connections to quadraticreciprocity and the Artin reciprocity theorem.) See Weil (1984).¹⁹ I’m indebted to Brian Conrad for illuminating conversations on this point.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!