13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

432 alasdair urquhartemerge from physics.’ Atiyah’s second approach is to ‘try to understand thephysics involved and enter into a dialogue with physicists concerned. This hasgreat potential benefits since we mathematicians can get behind the scenes andsee something <strong>of</strong> the stage machinery.’ It is the dialogue that emerges from thissecond approach that gives rise to the uneasiness <strong>of</strong> Jaffe and Quinn.The third approach mentioned by Atiyah is ‘to try to develop the physicson a rigorous basis so as to give a formal justification to the conclusions.’This corresponds quite closely to the second approach that I described inChapter 15, and <strong>of</strong> which I gave several examples above. The drawback <strong>of</strong>this third approach, according to Atiyah, is that ‘it is sometimes too slow tokeep up with the action. Depending on the maturity <strong>of</strong> the physical theoryand the technical difficulties involved, the gap between what is mathematicallyprovable and what is <strong>of</strong> current interest to physicists can be immense.’ Thefourth and most visionary idea is to ‘try to understand the deeper meanings <strong>of</strong>the physics-mathematics connection. Rather than view mathematics as a toolto establish physical theories, or physics as a way <strong>of</strong> pointing to mathematicaltruths, we can try to dig more deeply into the relation between them.’Whatever the attitude that one adopts as a mathematician or logician, it isclear that there is an immense amount <strong>of</strong> work to be done in this borderlinearea. The difficulties, both conceptual and mathematical, are severe, but theprizes to be gained through new understanding, are potentially immense.The last section <strong>of</strong> this chapter is devoted to the description <strong>of</strong> an areawhere the process <strong>of</strong> assimilation is incomplete, and which consequently posesdifficult problems <strong>of</strong> interpretation.16.7 The replica methodIn this section, I describe an anomalous object in the raw, so to speak. Inthe physics literature it is known as the Sherrington–Kirkpatrick (SK) model<strong>of</strong> spin glasses; it belongs to the class <strong>of</strong> models known generically as meanfield models. It is the exact analogue in the field <strong>of</strong> disordered systems <strong>of</strong> theCurie–Weiss model <strong>of</strong> ferromagnetism that I described in my introductorychapter.The SK model, like the Curie–Weiss model, is a caricature <strong>of</strong> certain realphysical systems. The key feature <strong>of</strong> such systems is that they involve largecollections <strong>of</strong> magnetic spin variables, where the interaction between thesevariables is not consistently ferromagnetic (favouring consistent orientation)but rather randomly ferromagnetic and antiferromagnetic (favouring opposite

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!