13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

418 alasdair urquhartSaunders Mac Lane, Benoit Mandelbrot, Karen Uhlenbeck, René Thom andWilliam Thurston. The reactions <strong>of</strong> both mathematicians and physicists to theintentionally provocative article are remarkably varied, and repay close study.One <strong>of</strong> the most interesting rejoinders came from Sir Michael Atiyah, whoremarked:My fundamental objection is that Jaffe and Quinn present a sanitized view <strong>of</strong>mathematics which condemns the subject to an arthritic old age ... if mathematicsis to rejuvenate itself and break exciting new ground it will have to allow for theexploration <strong>of</strong> new ideas and techniques which, in their creative phase, are likelyto be as dubious as in some <strong>of</strong> the great eras <strong>of</strong> the past. Perhaps we now havehigh standards <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> to aim at but, in the early stages <strong>of</strong> new developments,we must be prepared to act in more buccaneering style (Atiyah et al., 1994, p.1)Saunders Mac Lane made a vigorous reply to these startling comments <strong>of</strong>Atiyah, remarking that ‘a buccaneer is a pirate, and a pirate is <strong>of</strong>ten engagedin stealing. There may be such mathematicians now. ... We do not need suchstyles in mathematics’ (Mac Lane, 1997, p.150).There is a striking article (Cartier, 2000) by the distinguished Frenchmathematician Pierre Cartier that touches on many <strong>of</strong> the themes <strong>of</strong> the debatefollowing the publication <strong>of</strong> the Jaffe–Quinn article. In the introduction to hispaper, Cartier writes:The implicit philosophical belief <strong>of</strong> the working mathematician is today theHilbert–Bourbaki formalism. Ideally, one works within a closed system: thebasicprinciples are clearly enunciated once for all, including (that is an addition<strong>of</strong> twentieth century science) the formal rules <strong>of</strong> logical reasoning clothedin mathematical form. The basic principles include precise definitions <strong>of</strong> allmathematical objects ... My thesis is: there is another way <strong>of</strong> doing mathematics,equally successful, and the two methods should supplement each other and not fight. Thisother way bears various names: symbolic method, operational calculus, operatortheory ... Euler was the first to use such methods in his extensive study <strong>of</strong> infiniteseries, convergent as well as divergent. ... But the modern master was R. Feynmanwho used his diagrams, his disentangling <strong>of</strong> operators, his path integrals ... Themethod consists in stretching the formulas to their extreme consequences,resorting to some internal feeling <strong>of</strong> coherence and harmony. (Cartier, 2000,p.6)These remarks <strong>of</strong> Cartier are all the more startling if we remember that in the1950s, he was a core member <strong>of</strong> the Bourbaki group, contributing perhaps 200pages a year to the collective work.A superficial interpretation <strong>of</strong> the words <strong>of</strong> Atiyah and Cartier would bethat they are advocating a loosening <strong>of</strong> the standards <strong>of</strong> mathematical rigour.However, a careful examination <strong>of</strong> their articles reveals a more nuanced

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!