13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

eyond unification 153initially appeared to be different situations. Here the switch in conceptionfrom premise–conclusion pairs to derivations proves vital. Science advances ourunderstanding <strong>of</strong> nature by showing us how to derive descriptions <strong>of</strong> manyphenomena, using the same patterns <strong>of</strong> derivation again and again, and, indemonstrating this, it teaches us how to reduce the number <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong> facts thatwe have to accept as ultimate (or brute). So the criterion <strong>of</strong> unification I shall try toarticulate will be based on the idea that E(K) is a set <strong>of</strong> derivations that makes thebest trade<strong>of</strong>f between minimizing the number <strong>of</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> derivation employedand maximizing the number <strong>of</strong> conclusions generated. (Kitcher, 1989, p.432)We will come back to the distinction between arguments and derivationsand to a clarification <strong>of</strong> what E(K) is below.Local vs. global notions <strong>of</strong> explanation. In many accounts <strong>of</strong> explanation,including the Hempelian one, explanations are arguments. Arguments areidentified with pairs <strong>of</strong> premises and conclusions and can be assessed individuallywith respect to explanatoriness. Following Friedman, we would like to saythat whether an argument is an explanation is a local property, i.e. it does notdepend on more global constraints. Kitcher rejects both the identification <strong>of</strong>explanations as arguments conceived as above and the local characterization<strong>of</strong> explanation. The informal idea is that explanations qualify as such becausethey belong to the best systematization <strong>of</strong> our beliefs. Moreover, explanationsare not pairs <strong>of</strong> premises–conclusions, as in Hempel, but rather derivations:On the systematization account, an argument is considered as a derivation, as asequence <strong>of</strong> statements whose status (as a premise or as following from previousmembers in accordance with some specified rule) is clearly specified. An idealexplanation does not simply list the premises but shows how the premises yieldthe conclusion. (Kitcher, 1989, p.431)6.1.2 The formal details <strong>of</strong> the modelLet us make this more formal. Let us start with a set K <strong>of</strong> beliefs assumedconsistent and deductively closed (informally one can think <strong>of</strong> this as a set <strong>of</strong>statements endorsed by an ideal scientific community at a specific moment intime (Kitcher, 1989, p.431)). A systematization <strong>of</strong> K is any set <strong>of</strong> argumentswhich derive some sentences in K from other sentences in K. Theexplanatorystore over K, E(K), is the best systematization <strong>of</strong> K (Kitcher here makesan idealization by claiming that E(K) is unique). Corresponding to differentsystematizations we have different degrees <strong>of</strong> unification. The highest degree<strong>of</strong> unification is that given by E(K). But according to what criteria can asystematization be judged to be the best?Kitcher’s criteria for systematizations. Kitcher lists three criteria for judging thequality <strong>of</strong> a systematization , although as it turns out only two <strong>of</strong> them

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!