13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

356 colin mclartythen they could not use each other’s results without also verifying theequivalence <strong>of</strong> their chosen definitions. Any major paper uses scores<strong>of</strong> structures, each <strong>of</strong> which has many different set theoretic reductions(compare homology in Section 13.3.1). Checking so many equivalences isinfeasible. Leaving them implicit would court disaster. A set theoreticspecification may be used in some step <strong>of</strong> a pro<strong>of</strong> but those details mustbe rigorously irrelevant to the statement <strong>of</strong> the theorem (see discussion <strong>of</strong>Theorem 4).• Methods must handle structures at every level from natural numbers t<strong>of</strong>unctors by comparable means that readily relate any two levels.These methods are used in practice, by necessity, with deductive rigor, evenif they violate some philosophical theories.⁵ <strong>Practice</strong> also dispels the idea thatstructuralism abstracts away from intuitive content. Structuralist tools give themost direct known path from ‘pure’ content to rigor.Section 13.1 extends Resnik’s structuralism by the standard practice <strong>of</strong>identifying some structures as parts <strong>of</strong> others. Certain injections S 1 ↣S 2 <strong>of</strong>one structure S 1 into another S 2 are taken as identity preserving and thus asmaking S 1 a part <strong>of</strong> S 2 . We use textbook treatments <strong>of</strong> the real and complexnumbers to argue that such identity is not defined by any logical principles butby stipulation or tradition. This opens up a philosophical topic <strong>of</strong> explaininghow particular cases come to be accepted as identity preserving. Section 13.1.2argues that Shapiro’s distinction <strong>of</strong> systems and structures does not help tounderstand current practice.Section 13.2 pursues the original point <strong>of</strong> structuralist methods—definingstructures as themselves places in patterns <strong>of</strong> structures rather the way thatResnik describes in his later chapters. It takes polynomials as an example anddiscusses foundations. The ontology so far as it goes is far from philosophicallyclassical: The Leibniz law <strong>of</strong> identity fails as many individuals lack fullyindividuating properties. Nothing here prevents philosophers from goingbeyond practice and attributing a more classical ontology to mathematicalobjects. We know that mathematics can be re-interpreted in various waysto give it a classical ontology. But a further task faces anyone who claimsthat only classical ontology is conceptually sound: Either show that contraryto the appearances practice concretely does recognize such ontology; orexplain how conceptually unsound practice can succeed so well. Whateverposition one takes in debates over foundations and ‘structuralism,’ it remains⁵ See related arguments from practice against Quine’s ontology in Maddy (2005, p.450). CompareKrömer (2007, p. xv) on the way category theory became standard mathematics despite some clashwith <strong>of</strong>ficial ZF foundations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!