13.07.2015 Views

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

Mancosu - Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (Oxford, 2008).pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

what structuralism achieves 363Even existence pro<strong>of</strong>s usually specify elements only ‘in principle.’ Lang neveractually spells out in ZF detail what a polynomial is.So far the pattern or category <strong>of</strong> rings and morphisms is defined by a priorset theoretic definition <strong>of</strong> rings and morphisms. But standard tools can alsodescribe the pattern simply as a pattern ignoring, as Resnik says, the ‘internal’nature <strong>of</strong> rings and morphisms.¹³ Then a ring A is just a place in the pattern sothat, depending on the choice <strong>of</strong> foundations, A either has no elements in a settheoretic sense or it has them but they are unspecified and irrelevant. Eitherway morphisms are not functions defined on set theoretic elements. They arejust morphisms or more pictorially arrows in the pattern. The pattern includes aplace or places identifiable up to isomorphism as the ring Z <strong>of</strong> integers, anda place or places identifiable up to isomorphism as the ring Z[X] <strong>of</strong> integerpolynomials. Fact 1 has an analogue with Z in place <strong>of</strong> the real numbers Rwhich says we can define ‘elements’ <strong>of</strong> any ring A in a pattern theoretic senseto be the morphisms Z[X] → A. These correspond exactly to the classical settheoretic elements so that all the classical axioms on elements are verified, andthus all the classical theorems.The pattern <strong>of</strong> rings and ring morphisms, i.e. the category Ring, canbedefined in turn as a position in the pattern <strong>of</strong> categories and functors i.e. in thecategory <strong>of</strong> categories. Each ring A appearsasafunctorA : 1 → Ring where1istheterminal category. Ring morphisms f appear as functors f : 2 → Ringwhere 2 is the arrow category (Lawvere, 1966). Ring elements can still be definedby morphisms as in the previous paragraph. All the classical theorems on rings,elements, and morphisms reappear at this level. There is no obstacle to takingany one <strong>of</strong> these levels as basic with the others derived from it.13.3 The unifying spirit13.3.1 A few uses <strong>of</strong> patternsThese structural methods have deep roots in practice. As a notable example,topology by the 1920s relied on a booming but chaotic notion <strong>of</strong> homology.There were many versions.¹⁴ Topologists assumed that results proved for oneversion would normally hold for all—but they could not say just what was‘normal’ here. Some versions <strong>of</strong> homology were later proved exactly equivalent¹³ Universal algebra defines the category up to isomorphism (Lawvere, 1963). Monads define it noteven up to isomorphism but up to equivalence (Mac Lane, 1998, Ch.6).¹⁴ e.g. the Čech, Vietoris, and singular theories <strong>of</strong> Chapter 8 in Hocking and Young (1961) allexisted before the unifying category theoretic language <strong>of</strong> Chapter 7.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!